[go: up one dir, main page]
More Web Proxy on the site http://driver.im/ Skip to main content
Log in

”The Unavoidable Interaction Between the Object and the Measuring Instruments”: Reality, Probability, and Nonlocality in Quantum Physics

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article aims to contribute to the ongoing task of clarifying the relationships between reality, probability, and nonlocality in quantum physics. It is in part stimulated by Khrennikov’s argument, in several communications, for “eliminating the issue of quantum nonlocality” from the analysis of quantum entanglement. I argue, however, that the question may not be that of eliminating but instead that of further illuminating this issue, a task that can be pursued by relating quantum nonlocality to other key features of quantum phenomena. I suggest that the following features of quantum phenomena and quantum mechanics, distinguishing them from classical phenomena and classical physics—(1) the irreducible role of measuring instruments in defining quantum phenomena, (2) discreteness, (3) complementarity, (4) entanglement, (5) quantum nonlocality, and (6) the irreducibly probabilistic nature of quantum predictions—are all interconnected, so that it is difficult to give an unconditional priority to any one of them. To argue this case, I shall consider quantum phenomena and quantum mechanics from a nonrealist or, in terms adopted here, “reality-without-realism” (RWR) perspective. This perspective extends Bohr’s view, grounded in his analysis of the irreducible role of measuring instruments in the constitution of quantum phenomena.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
£29.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price includes VAT (United Kingdom)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. My argument will be restricted to the standard QM. Other theories of quantum phenomena, such as Bohmian mechanics, will only be mentioned in passing. I shall also put aside the complexities involved in using such terms as “theory,” “model,” or “mathematical model,” considered from the RWR perspective in [1, pp. 6–10]

  2. Khrennikov, in [13, 14] in part responds to the argumentation of this author in [16, 17]. The present article is a revised version of [17]. While still responding to Khrennikov, it offers a more independent argument and new concepts, in particular that of quantum indefinitiveness.

  3. Thus, he changed his view even before the lecture, given in September 1927, was published in April 1928 [20]. Bohr, notably, dated the published version 1927 when it was reprinted in his book, Atomic Theory and the Description of Nature [20], now the first volume of [19].

  4. I have considered different versions of Bohr’s interpretation in [22]. It is worth noting that there is no single Copenhagen interpretation, as even Bohr changed his views a few times. It is more fitting to speak, as Heisenberg did, of “the Copenhagen spirit of the quantum theory” [23, p. iv]. This spirit designates a spectrum of interpretations that share some, but not all, of their features.

  5. The literature on the subject is extensive, and my limits here only allow me to mention a very small portion of it.

  6. It is worth noting that Khrennikov, too, brings into consideration complementarity and the role of Planck’s constant, h [15].

  7. Two such cases are “the continuity axiom” of L. Hardy’s derivation [27] and “the purification postulate” of that of D’Ariano et al. [28].

  8. See, for example, [29, 30]. I have discussed this subject in detail in [1, pp. 33–34].

  9. While in physics the primary reality considered is that of matter, a reality, including a reality without realism, can be mental, for example, in mathematics [32, pp. 203–210].

  10. Although terms “realist” and “ontological” sometimes designate more diverging concepts, they are close in their meaning and will be used interchangeably here.

  11. One could in principle see the assumption of the existence or reality of something to which a theory can relate without representing it as a form of realism. This use of the term is found in advocating interpretations of QM that are nonrealist in the present sense (e.g., [34,35,36]), although none of these authors entertains the strong RWR view. In any event, I would argue that the present definition is more in accord with most understandings of realism in physics and philosophy.

  12. Both Dirac [41] and von Neumann [42], followed Bohr’s Como argument or, in any event, adopted the same type of view, allowing for realism and classical causality in considering the independent behavior of quantum objects, with probabilities only introduced by measurement (see [25, pp. 197–214], [7, p. 1279].

  13. These qualifications in part explain the history of questioning of the idea of causality in fundamental physics, while allowing for the type of view of classical physics or relativity termed here classically causal, beginning with Russell’s 1913 essay [44]. See [45] for a reconsideration of Russell’s argument from a contemporary perspective, allied with structural realism [33]. As will be seen, in the case of quantum causality, one could speak of events as causes.

  14. There is yet another alternative, that of simply disregarding such questions, captured by N. D. Mermin’s often cited maxim “shut up and calculate,” an attitude not adopted by Mermin himself, who said on the same occassion: “But I will not shut up” [46, p. 24].

  15. The concept of quantum indefinitiveness is different from A. Shimony’s realist concept of “objective indefiniteness,” which sounds similar [47]. Shimony’s concept implies a statement concerning a relation of between individual quantum events, a relation established by QM. The concept of quantum indefinitiveness is independent of QM. Shimony’s concept is noteworthy as revealing subtler dimensions of realism in quantum theory. See [48] for an instructive discussion.

  16. For discussion of the concept of quantum field from the RWR perspective, see [5].

  17. The concept “quantum object” could be defined otherwise, for example, on more realist lines, as, in part via Shimony’s concept of objective indefiniteness, mentioned above, in [48].

  18. A somewhat similar argument concerning the stratified character of the reality defining quantum phenomena, if without adopting the RWR view, was proposed in [52].

  19. The nature of this “amplification” is part of the problem of the transition from the quantum to the classical, which and related subjects, such as “decoherence, ” are beyond my scope here.

  20. The difference between the statistical and probabilistic (such as Bayesian) views of QM would require a separate treatment. Khrennikov, in the works cited here, adoptes a statistical view, on more realist lines, as does, on RWR lines, the present author [4, 7]. Quantum Bayesianism, QBism, offers an RWR-type Bayesian approach [35]. RWR-type statistical interpretations of QM are uncommon. A compelling example of a statistical interpretation that may be interpreted along RWR lines, even if it is not by the authors themselves, is offered in [54]. Their position appears to allow for this interpretation because they argue that one should only interpret outcomes of pointer indications, and leave the richer quantum structure, which has many ways of expressing the same identities, without interpretation. In RWR-type interpretations, this structure would only be seen as that enabling statistical predictions, without representing the ultimate reality responsible for the outcomes of quantum experiments and hence pointer indications. Finally, there are also arguments (which are, it follows, realist) for classical causality in the case of discrete events, arguments advocated, for example, by L. Smolin, following R. Sorkin [55, pp. 257–261]. These arguments, in my view, pose problems, beginning with that of establishing discontinuous physical mechanisms by means of which classical causality can be established for such events, although one could have mathematics for predictions concerning them. It is not discreteness but classical causality that is the main difficulty.

  21. See [56], for an assessment of Heisenberg’s overall later views of QM, including in [49].

  22. This observation, as Wheeler notes, anticipates the delayed choice experiment [21, pp. 182–192].

  23. This point appears to have been missed or not addressed either in commentaries on Bohr or by treatments of quantum measurement elsewhere. Subtle as it is, Schrödinger’s analysis of quantum measurement in his cat-paradox paper does not consider this point [53, pp. 158–159]. Von Neumann’s analysis comes close, but, while it is conceivable that von Neumann realized this point, he did not comment on it, and some of his statements suggest a realist view, which attributes the measured quantity to the object at the time of measurement [42, pp. 355–356].

  24. I am indebted to D’Ariano for drawing my attention to the significance of considering composite systems in quantum theory, the point emphasized in his recent works (some of which are cited here), in contrast to other quantum-informational approaches to quantum foundations.

  25. This situation is also responsible for what is known as “contextuality,” which is a statistical concept. I have considered the relationships between complementarity and contextuality from the RWR perspective in [6].

  26. One might also note, along Bayesian lines, that predictions with any probability are only meaningful insofar as those who made them or know of them are still alive.

  27. That a prediction with probability equal to unity is not the same as establishing the reality of what is so predicted has been stressed by quantum Bayesians (QBists), on the grounds of the subjective nature of Bayesian probability, rather than the reasoning used here (e.g., [35, 46, pp. 231–238]).

  28. I only cite some key earlier experiments. There have been numerous experiments performed since, some in order to find loopholes in these and subsequent experiments.

  29. The literature dealing with these subjects is immense. Among the standard treatments are [69,70,71,72,73]. There are also realist and causal views of quantum entanglement and correlations, either in realist interpretations of QM, such as the many worlds interpretation, or in alternative theories, such as Bohmian mechanics or that of classical random fields [7, 74]. Superdeterminism is another realist view, which explains away the complexities discussed here by denying an independent decision of performing one or the other EPR measurements (e.g., [75, 76]).

  30. I have considered Bohr’s reply in detail previously [3, pp. 136–154], [22, pp. 107–136], [25, pp. 237–312] . The present discussion, however, modifies these treatments in several respects.

  31. EPR’s actual argument is more elaborate. They derive a contradiction between the assumption that QM is complete and the assumption of the impossibility of attaching definite values to both variables in question, which, since this impossibility is inherent in QM, implies that QM is uncomplete. But this conclusion is essentially the same as stated by Bohr here. Even though one can predict (exactly) the two quantities considered only alternatively, EPR still contend that both quantities correspond to the elements of reality jointly pertaining to \(S_{2}\), according to their criterion, which does not require simultaneity of such measurements or predictions, a requrement that would, in their their view, impliy Einstein-nonlocality [8, p. 141] . QM, however, only allows one to predict either one or the other of these two quantities. Hence, it is incomplete, because it cannot predict all that is possible to establish as real, unless it is Einstein-nonlocal.

  32. This fact was important for Khrennikov’s arguments concerning quantum nonlocality. It was also recently stressed, on more realist lines, by Grangier (e.g., [77]).

  33. As has been noted by several authors, Schrödinger arguably the first of them [53, p. 160] , one could simultaneously make the position measurement on \(S_{1}\) and the momentum measurement on \(S_{2}\), and thus simultaneously predict (ideally exactly) the second variable for each system, the momentum for \(S_{1}\) and the position for \(S_{2}\). This determination, however, is not simultaneous in the same location, and measuring the complementary variable instead of the predicted one in either location would irrevocably preclude one from verifying this prediction and would define a different reality.

  34. The argumentation just given complicates speaking, as is common, of entangled objects as forming “an indivisible whole.” Bohr never does so, although his reply to EPR has been misread in this way, by confusing Bohr’s use of this language for describing a phenomenon in his sense as forming an indivisible whole with the quantum object considered. Bohr’s concept of phenomenon was introduced later. But, if one applies, and one can, this concept to Bohr’s argument in his reply to EPR, a measurement performed on \(S_{1}\) forms an indivisible whole composed of \(S_{1}\) and the measuring instrument used, but does not in any way involve \(S_{2}\). It only enables one to make a prediction concerning \(S_{2}\) and the corresponding possible future phenomenon. A prediction is, however, not a phenomenon, only a measurement is; and a measurement on \(S_{2}\) would establish its own phenomenon, with its own indivisible wholeness between \(S_{2}\) and the measuring instrument.

References

  1. Plotnitsky, A.: “The Heisenberg method”: geometry, algebra, and probability in quantum theory. Entropy 20, 656 (2018). https://doi.org/10.3390/e20090656

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  2. Plotnitsky, A.: A matter of principle: the principles of quantum theory, Dirac’s equation, and quantum information. Fond. Phys. 45(10), 1222–1268 (2014)

    ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Plotnitsky, A.: The Principles of Quantum Theory, from Planck’s Quanta to the Higgs Boson: The Nature of Quantum Reality and the Spirit of Copenhagen. Springer, New York (2016)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  4. Plotnitsky, A.: Structure without law: from Heisenberg’s matrix mechanics to structural nonrealism. Mind and Matter 16(1), 59–96 (2018b)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Plotnitsky, A.: Transitions without connections: quantum states, from Bohr and Heisenberg to quantum information theory. Eur. Phys. J. (2019). https://doi.org/10.1140/epjst/e2018-800082-6

  6. Plotnitsky, A.: Spooky predictions at a distance: reality, complementarity and contextuality in quantum theory. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. A 377, 20190089 (2019b)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  7. Plotnitsky, A., Khrennikov, A.: Reality without realism: on the ontological and epistemological architecture of quantum mechanics. Found. Phys. 25(10), 1269–1300 (2015)

    ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., Rosen, N.: Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? In: Wheeler, J.A., Zurek, W.H. (eds.) Quantum Theory and Measurement, pp. 138–141. Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1983 (1935)

  9. Bohr, N.: Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Phys. Rev. 48, 696–702 (1935)

    ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Khrennikov, A.: Get rid of nonlocality from quantum physics. Entropy 21(8), 806 (2019a)

    ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  11. Khrennikov, A.: Quantum versus classical entanglement: eliminating the issue of quantum nonlocality. arXiv: 1909.00267 (2019)

  12. Khrennikov, A.: Echoing the recent Google success: Foundational Roots of Quantum Supremacy. arXiv: 1911.10337 (2019)

  13. Khrennikov, A.: Two faced Janus of quantum nonlocality. arXiv: 2002.01977v1 [quantum-ph] (2020)

  14. Khrennikov, A.: Quantum versus classical entanglement: eliminating the issue of quantum nonlocality. Found. Phys. (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-020-00319-7

  15. Khrennikov, A.: Quantum postulate vs. quantum nonlocality: is [the] devil in \(h\)? arXiv: 2003.05718v1 [quantum-ph] (2020)

  16. Plotnitsky, A.: “Without in any way disturbing the system:” Illuminating the issue of quantum nonlocality. arXiv:1912.03842v1 [quant-ph] (2019)

  17. Plotnitsky, A.: “Without in any way disturbing the system:” Illuminating the issue of quantum nonlocality. arXiv:1912.03842v2 [quant-ph] (2020)

  18. Bohr, N.: On the constitution of atoms and Molecules (Part 1). Philos. Mag. 26(151), 1–25 (1913)

    ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Bohr, N.: The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, 3 vols. Ox Bow Press, Woodbridge (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Bohr, N.: Atomic Theory and the Description of Nature. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1934)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. Wheeler, J.A.: Law without law. In: Wheeler, J.A., Zurek, W.H. (eds.) Quantum Theory and Measurement, pp. 182–216. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1983)

    Google Scholar 

  22. Plotnitsky, A.: Niels Bohr and Complementarity: An Introduction. Springer, New York (2012)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  23. Heisenberg, W.: The Physical Principles of the Quantum Theory (tr. Eckhart, K., Hoyt, F.C.). Dover, New York, rpt. 1949 (1930)

  24. Born, M.:The Einstein-Born Letters (tr.Born, I.). Walker, New York (2005)

  25. Plotnitsky, A.: Epistemology and Probability: Bohr. Heisenberg, Schrödinger and the Nature of Quantum-Theoretical Thinking. Springer, New York (2009)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  26. Einstein, A.: Autobiographical Notes (tr. Schillp, P. A.). Open Court, La Salle, 1991 (1949)

  27. Hardy, L.: Quantum mechanics from five reasonable axioms. arXiv: quant-ph/0101012 (2001)

  28. D’Ariano, G.M., Chiribella, G., Perinotti, P.: Quantum Theory from First Principles: An Informational Approach. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2017)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  29. Spekkens, R.W.: Evidence for the epistemic view of quantum states: a toy theory. Phys. Rev. A 75(3), 032110 (2007)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  30. Spekkens, R.W.: Quasi-quantization: classical statistical theories with an epistemic restriction. In: Chiribella, G., Spekkens, R.W. (eds.) Quantum Theory: Informational Foundations and Foils, pp. 83–136. Springer, New York (2016)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  31. Wittgenstein, L.: Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (tr. C. K. Ogden). Routledge, London, rpt. 1924 (1985)

  32. Plotnitsky, A.: On the concept of curve: geometry and algebra, from mathematical modernity to mathematical modernism. In: Papadopoulos, A., Dani, S. (eds.) Geometry in History. Springer, Berlin (2019)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  33. Ladyman, J.: Structural realism. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 edition), Zalta, E. N. (ed), plato.stanford.edu/structural-realism (2016)

  34. Cabello, A.: Interpretations of quantum theory: a map of madness. In: Lombardi, O., Fortin, S., Holik, F., López, C. (eds.) What is Quantum Information?, pp. 138–144. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2017)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  35. Fuchs, C.A., Mermin, N.D., Schack, R.: An introduction to QBism with an application to the locality of quantum mechanics. Am. J. Phys. 82, 749 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1119/1.4874855

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  36. Werner, R.F.: Comment on ‘What Bell did’. J. Phys. A 47, 424011 (2014)

    ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  37. Kant, I.: Critique of Pure Reason (tr. Guyer, P., Wood, A.W). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1997)

  38. Heisenberg, W.: Quantum-theoretical re-interpretation of kinematical and mechanical relations. In: Van der Waerden, B.L. (ed.) Sources of Quantum Mechanics, pp. 261–272. Dover, New York, 1968 (1925)

  39. Born, M., Jordan, P.: Zur Quantenmechanik. Z. für Physik 34, 858 (1925)

    ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  40. Mehra, J., Rechenberg, H.: The Historical Development of Quantum Theory, 6 vols. Springer, Berlin (2001)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  41. Dirac, P. A. M.: The Principles of Quantum Mechanics. Clarendon, Oxford, rpt. 1995 (1958)

  42. Von Neumann, J.: Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics (tr. R. T. Beyer). Princeton University Press, Princeton, rpt. 1983 (1932)

  43. Bohr, N.: Causality and complementarity. In Faye, J., Folse, H.J. (eds.) The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, Volume 4: Causality and Complementarity, Supplementary Papers, pp. 83–91. Ox Bow Press, Woodbridge, 1994 (1937)

  44. Russell, B.: On the Notion of Cause. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, vol. 13, pp. 1–26 (1913)

  45. Ross, D., Spurrett, D.: Notions of cause: Russell’s thesis revisited. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 58(1), 45–76 (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  46. Mermin, N.D.: Why Quark Rhymes with Pork: And Other Scientific Diversions. Cambridge University Pres, Cambridge (2016)

    Google Scholar 

  47. Shimony, A.: The reality of the quantum world. Sci. Am. 258(1), 46–53 (1988)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  48. Jaeger, G.: Quantum Objects: Non-local Correlations, Causality and Objective Indefiniteness in the Quantum World. Springer, New York (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  49. Heisenberg, W.: Physics and Philosophy: The Revolution in Modern Science. Harper and Row, New York (1962)

    Google Scholar 

  50. Kalckar, J.: Niels Bohr and his younger disciples. In: Rozental, S. (ed.) Niles Bohr: His Life and Work as Seen by His Friends and Colleagues, pp. 227–239. North Holland, Amsterdam (1967)

    Google Scholar 

  51. Arndt, M., Nairz, O., Voss-Andreae, J., Keller, C., van der Zouw, G., Zeilinger, A.: Wave particle duality of C60. Nature 401, 680–682 (1999)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  52. Rovelli, C.: Relational quantum mechanics. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 35(8), 1637–1678 (1996)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  53. Schrödinger, E.: The present situation in quantum mechanics. In Wheeler, J.A., Zurek, W.H. (eds.) Quantum Theory and Measurement, pp. 152–167. Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1983 (1935)

  54. Allahverdyan, A. E., Balian, R., Nieuwenhuizen, T. M.: A sub-ensemble theory of ideal quantum measurement processes. Ann. Phys. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.aop.2016.11.001 (2016)

  55. Smolin, L.: Einstein’s Unfinished Revolution: The Search for What Lies Beyond the Quantum. Penguin, New York (2018)

    Google Scholar 

  56. Jaeger, G.: Quantum contextuality in the Copenhagen approach. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. A.https://doi.org/10.1098/rsta.2019.0025 (2019)

  57. Wigner, E.: On unitary representations of the inhomogeneous Lorentz group. Ann. Math. 40, 149–204 (1939)

    ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  58. Bohr, N.: The causality problem in atomic physics. In: Faye, J., Folse, H.J. (eds.) The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, Volume 4: Causality and Complementarity, Supplementary Papers, pp. 94–121. Ox Bow Press, Woodbridge, 1987 (1938)

  59. Plotnitsky, A.: ‘Dark materials to create more worlds’: on causality in classical physics, quantum physics, and nanophysics. J. Comput. Theor. Nanosci. 8(6), 983–997 (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  60. Brukner, C.: Quantum causality. Nat. Phys. 10, 259–263 (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  61. Hardy, L.: A formalism-local framework for general probabilistic theories, including quantum theory. arXiv:1005.5164 [quant-ph] (2010)

  62. D’Ariano, G.M.: Causality re-established. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. A 376, 20170313. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsta.2017.0313 (2018)

  63. Barbour, J.B.: The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Physics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  64. Gomes, H. de A.: Back to Parmenides. arXiv: 1603.01574 (2016)

  65. Aspect, A., Dalibard, J., Roger, G.: Experimental test of Bell’s inequalities using time varying analyzers. Phys. Rev. Lett. 49, 1804–1807 (1982)

    ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  66. Greenberger, D.M., Horne, M.A., Zeilinger, A.: Going beyond Bell’s theorem. In: Kafatos, M. (ed.) Bell’s Theorem. Quantum Theory and Conceptions of the Universe, pp. 69–72. Kluwer, Dordrecht (1989)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  67. Greenberger, D.M., Horne, M.A., Shimony, A., Zeilinger, A.: Bell’s Theorem without inequalities. Am. J. Phys 58, 1131–1142 (1990)

    ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  68. Hardy, L.: Nonlocality for two particles without inequalities for almost all entangled states. Phys. Rev. Lett. 71, 1665–1668 (1993)

    ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  69. Bell, J.S.: Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2004)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  70. Cushing, J.T., McMullin, E. (eds.): Philosophical Consequences of Quantum Theory: Reflections on Bell’s Theorem. Notre Dame University Press, Notre Dame (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  71. Ellis, J., Amati, D. (eds.): Quantum Reflections. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2000)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  72. Mermin, N.D.: Boojums All the Way Through: Communicating Science in a Prosaic Age. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1990)

    Google Scholar 

  73. Brunner N., Gühne O., Huber, M (eds): Special issue on 50 years of Bell’s theorem. J. Phys. A 42, 424024 (2014)

  74. Khrennikov, A.: Quantum probabilities and violation of CHSH-inequality from classical random signals and threshold type detection scheme. Prog. Theor. Phys. 128, 31–58 (2012)

    ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  75. Hooft, G.: Quantum mechanics and determinism. In: Frampton, P., Ng, J. (eds.) Particles, Strings, and Cosmology, pp. 275–285. Rinton Press, Princeton, NJ (2001)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  76. ’t Hooft, G.: Time, the arrow of time, and quantum mechanics. arXiv: 1804.01383 (2018)

  77. Farouki, N., Grangier, F.: The Einstein-Bohr debate: finding a common ground of understanding. arXiv:1907.11267 (2019)

  78. Einstein, A.: Remarks to the essays appearing in this collective volume. In Schillp, P.A. (ed.) Albert Einstein: Philosopher–Scientist, pp. 663–688. Tudor, New York (1949)

    Google Scholar 

  79. Einstein, A.: Physics and reality. J. Frankl. Inst. 221, 349–382 (1936)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to G. M. D’Ariano, C. A. Fuchs, P. Grangier, L. Hardy, G. Jaeger, A. Khrennikov, and T. Nieuwenhuizen for helpful discussions concerning the subjects considered in this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Arkady Plotnitsky.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Plotnitsky, A. ”The Unavoidable Interaction Between the Object and the Measuring Instruments”: Reality, Probability, and Nonlocality in Quantum Physics. Found Phys 50, 1824–1858 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-020-00353-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-020-00353-5

Keywords

Navigation