Abstract
We can witness the recent surge of interest in the interaction between cognitive science, philosophy of science, and aesthetics on the problem of representation. This naturally leads us to rethinking the achievements of Goodman’s monumental book Languages of Art. For, there is no doubt that no one else contributed more than Goodman to throw a light on the cognitive function of art. Ironically, it could be also Goodman who has been the stumbling block for a unified theory of representation. In this paper, I shall contrast the ways how differently misrepresentation has been treated in cognitive science, aesthetics, and philosophy of science. And I shall show that it is Goodman’s unnecessary separation of resemblance and representation in art that made such a difference. As a conclusion, I will indicate some of the most promising projects toward the unified theory of representation the revolt against Goodman’s rejection of resemblance theories might promise to us.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
Fodor (1986, 1987), Barwise (1986, 1989). Fodor thinks that the theory of information held by Dretske and articulated by Barwise and Perry treats the information content of a situation as the basic notion. In this theory, the information content is non-perspectival, receiver neutral, intrinsic, and non-intentional. On the other hand, he claims, what are needed in cognitive science are the notions of information displayed by a signal, the information encoded by the signal, and the information in the signal that is available to the agent. They are perspectival, receiver relative, non-intrinsic, and intentional. Barwise sensitively responds to such a characterization of their theory, especially as behavioristic. He also launches a counterattack on Fodor’s ideas of lingua mentis, which is not our present concern.
Interestingly, Fodor becomes more and more favorable to the possibility of the information-based theory of meaning. In particular, he seems to withdraw his criticism formulated as the naturalization problem (Fodor 1990, 131, n. 3). Be that as it may, the naturalization problem is not our current concern.
I mistakenly claimed that the relevance of resemblance to representation is simply taken for granted in philosophy of science. But such a claim is “misleading in the sense that theories of verisimilitude explicitly define similarity relations between states of affairs or possible worlds and explicitly analyze case studies of misrepresenting idealizations”. I am indebted to an anonymous reviewer for this point.
Of the two analogies he has in mind, I am going to discuss only the first one, which concerns abstraction and idealization in science.
Chakravartty uses Stathis Psillos’ summary as a point of departure: “A description D ... is approximately true of [a state] S if there is another state S’ such that S and S’ are linked by specific conditions of approximation, and D ... is true of S”’ [ibid., p. 34; Psillos 1999, p. 277].
We already noted that at a crucial point Perini is indebted to File’s distinction. And, so is Newall (2010, 102, n. 4). So, it seems advisable to grant a fair hearing to Files for the reasons why we need to criticize and modify Goodman’s rejection of resemblance theory.
References
Bailer-Jones, D. (2009). Scientific models in philosophy of science. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Barwise, J. (1986). Information and circumstance: A reply to fodor. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 27, 324–338.; Reprinted in Barwise (1989).
Barwise, J. (1989). Situation in logic. Stanford: CSLI.
Barwise, J., et al. (1993). Constraints, channels, and the flow of information. In P. Aczel (Ed.), Situation theory and its applications (Vol. 3). Stanford, CA: CSLI.
Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1985). Shifting situations and shaken attitudes. Linguistics and Philosophy, 8, 105–161.
Barwise, J., & Seligman, J. (1993). The rights and wrongs of natural regularity. In J. E. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives 8. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.
Barwise, J., & Seligman, J. (1997). Information flow. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Blumson, B. (2009). Images, intentionality and inexistence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79(3), 522–538.
Chakravartty, A. (2010a). Truth and representation in science: Two inspirations from art. In R. Frigg & M. C. Hunter (Eds.), Beyond mimesis and convention (pp. 33–50). Boston: Springer.
Chakravartty, A. (2010b). Informational versus functional theories of scientific representation. Synthese, 172, 197–213.
Chokr, N. N. (1993). Nelson goodman on truth, relativism, and criteria of rightness or why we should dispense with truth and adopt rightness? Dialectica, 47(1), 55–73.
Cohnitz, D., & Rossberg, M. (Eds.). (2006). Nelson Goodman. Montreal, Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press.
Downes, S. M. (2009). Models, pictures, and unified accounts of representation: Lessons from aesthetics for philosophy of science. Perspectives on Science, 17(4), 417–428.
Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Files, C. (1996). Goodman’s rejection of resemblance. British Journal of Aesthetics, 36(4), 398–412.
Fodor, J. A. (1984). Semantics Wisconsin style. Synthese, 59, 231–250.
Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. New York: Thomas Crowell.
Fodor, J. (1986). Information and association. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 27, 307–323.
Fodor, J. (1987). A situated grandmother? Mind & Language, 2, 64–81.
Fodor, J. (1990). Information and representation. In P. Hanson (ed.), pp. 175–197.
Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1990). The theory of contents and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1994). The elm and the expert. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Godfrey-Smith, P. (1989). Misinformation. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 19(4), 533–550.
Goodman, N. (1972). Problems and projects. Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Company Inc.
Goodman, N. (1976). Languages of art (2nd ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett.
Goodman, N. (1978). Ways of worldmaking. Indianapolis: Hackett.
Hanson, P. (Ed.). (1990). Information, language, and cognition. New York: Oxford University Press.
Hopkins, R. (1994). Resemblance and,isrepresentation. Mind, 103, 421–438.
Hopkins, R. (1998). Picture, image and experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hyman, J. (2000). Pictorial art and visual experience. British Journal of Aesthetics, 40(1), 21–45.
Jones, M. R. (2005). Idealization and abstraction: A framework. In M. R. Jones & N. Cartwright (Eds.), Idealization XII–correcting the model: Idealization and abstraction in the sciences (Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of Sciences and the Humanities) (pp. 173–217). Amsterdam/New York, NY: Rodopi.
Kaplan, D. (1969). Quantifying in. Synthese, 19, 178–214.
Kulvicki, J. V. (2006). On images: Their structure and content. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Lopes, D. (1996). Understanding pictures. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Newall, M. (2010). Pictorial resemblance. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 68(2), 91–103.
Niiniluoto, I. (1987). Truthlikeness. Dortrecht: Reidel.
Niiniluoto, I. (1998). Verisimilitude: The third period. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49, 1–29.
Oddie, G. (1986). Likeness to truth. Boston: Reidel.
Perini, L. (2005). The truth in pictures. Philosophy of Science, 72, 262–285.
Perlman, M. (2000). Conceptual flux: Mental representation, misrepresentation, and conceptual change. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Popper, K. (1972). Objective knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.
Rollins, M. (1999). Pictorial representation: When cognitive science meets aesthetics. Philosophical Psychology, 12(4), 388–413.
Schurz, G. (2011). Verisimilitude and belief revision. With a focus on the relevant element account. Erkenntnis, 75(2), 203–221.
Van Fraassen, B. C. (2008). Scientific representation: Paradoxes of perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Pres.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Park, W. Misrepresentation in Context. Found Sci 19, 363–374 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-014-9345-3
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-014-9345-3