Abstract
In this paper, we contrast direct and representative democracy. In a direct democracy, individuals have the opportunity to vote over the alternatives in every choice problem the population faces. In a representative democracy, the population commits to a candidate ex ante who will then make choices on its behalf. While direct democracy is normatively appealing, representative democracy is the far more common institution because of its practical advantages. The key question, then, is whether representative democracy succeeds in implementing the choices that the group would make under direct democracy. We find that, in general, it does not. We model a population as a distribution of voters with strict preferences over a finite set of alternatives and a candidate as a strict ordering of those alternatives that serves as a binding, contingent plan of action. We focus on the case where the direct democracy choices of the population are consistent with a strict ordering of the alternatives. We show that even in this case, where the normative recommendation of direct democracy is clearest, representative democracy may not elect the candidate with this ordering.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
There is a rich existing literature on representative democracy, though in general this literature has focused more on voting power and proportional representation. See, for example, Tullock (1967), Chamberlin and Courant (1983), Monroe (1995), Felsenthal and Machover (1998), and Potthof and Brams (1998).
This is the case where the tournament over alternatives is not only complete and asymmetric, but also transitive.
In the language of Edward Burke, this is a delegate model of representative democracy, rather than a trustee model, as the elected official is committed to enacting the platform selected by the voters. See Maskin and Tirole (2004) or Fox and Shotts (2009) for discussions of the delegate versus trustee debate.
We restrict attention to populations with no ties in the majority relation, guaranteeing a complete and asymmetric tournament. This is similar to assuming an odd number of voters in the more common discrete population framework.
This is consistent with the approach of Laffond and Lainé (2000), who also focus on the case where majority preferences over alternatives produce an ordering.
This definition means we employ relative majority rule. We could alternatively define our tournaments in terms of absolute majority rule. Under this assumption, we would have \(\pi ^{\prime }T^{\lambda }\pi \) only if a majority of voters are strictly closer to \(\pi ^{\prime }\) than \(\pi \). For absolute majority rule, if neither candidate is closer to more than half of the population, the two candidates would tie in the tournament relation.
In our framework, voters will often be indifferent between candidates. Each voter has a set of indifference curves: a voter most prefers the candidate with his own ordering, then he equally prefers all candidates with whom he disagrees about the choice from one pair of alternatives, and next he equally prefers all candidates with whom he disagrees about the choice from two pairs of candidates, etc.
Given the large amount of indifference in our population, choosing to use absolute majority rule would result in a large number of ties in our tournaments over orderings. These ties would disregard the information we have on the voters who are not indifferent. For instance, in a tie between candidate \(\pi \) and \(\pi ^{\prime }\), we may have that 30 % of the voters are indifferent between candidate \(\pi \) and candidate \(\pi ^{\prime }\), 49 % of the voters prefer \(\pi \) to \(\pi ^{\prime }\), and only 21 % of voters prefer \(\pi ^{\prime }\) to \(\pi \). Despite the large disparity in the number of voters that strictly prefer \(\pi \) to \(\pi ^{\prime }\) as opposed to \(\pi ^{\prime }\) to \(\pi \), these two orderings would tie in the tournament relation. By using relative majority rule, we use this information on strict preference, even in the cases where large subsets of voters are indifferent between the two candidates.
Note that a positive result (consistency between these forms of direct and representative democracy) could be derived if one chose to use the less selective top cycle as the tournament solution concept. We discuss this in more detail in Sect. 3.
The other technical difference is that Laffond and Lainé (2000) restrict the set of preference extension rules (mappings from preferences over alternatives into preferences over candidates) they consider to those rules that produce complete linear orders over candidates, explicitly disallowing indifference. We map preferences over alternatives into preferences over candidates using the Kemeny distance, and we allow voters to be indifferent over candidates whose orderings are equidistant from their own. In this way, the particular mapping we study is not in their permissible class of preference extension rules.
Lainé et al. (2015) prove a stronger version of this proposition, showing that the top cycle not only fails Kemeny-stability (similar in spirit to what we show here), but also fails their more general hyper-stability property. See Theorem 6 in their paper.
References
Ahn DS, Oliveros S (2012) Combinatorial voting. Econometrica 80(1):89–141
Arrow KJ (1951) Social choice and individual values. Wiley, New York
Baldiga KA, Green JR (2013) Assent-maximizing social choice. Soc Choice Welf 40(2):439–460
Banks JS (1985) Sophisticated voting outcomes and agenda control. Soc Choice Welf 4:295–306
Besley T, Coate S (2008) Issue Unbundling via Citizens’ Initiatives. Q J Political Sci 3(4):379–397
Black D (1948) On the rationale of group decision making. J Political Econ 56:23–34
Bossert W, Storcken T (1992) Strategy-proofness of social welfare functions: the use of the Kemeny distance between preference orderings. Soc Choice Welf 9:345–360
Bowser JD (2012) Initiative, referendum, and recall. In: National conference of state legislatures. http://www.ncsl.org/legislatures-elections/elections/initiative-referendum-and-recall-overview.aspx
Brandt F, Geist C, Harrenstein P, Working paper (2015) A note on the McKelvey uncovered set and Pareto optimality
Chamberlin J, Courant P (1983) Representative deliberations and representative decisions: proportional representation and the borda rule. Am Political Sci Rev 77(3):718–733
Copeland AH (1951) A reasonable social welfare function (unpublished manuscript)
Daniels HE (1969) Round robin tournament scores. Biometrika 56:295–299
Dasgupta P, Maskin E (2008) On the robustness of majority rule. J Eur Econ Assoc 6(5):949–973
Felsenthal D, Machover M (1998) The measurement of voting power: theory and practice, problems, and paradoxes. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham
Fishburn P (1977) Condorcet social choice functions. SIAM J Appl Math 33:469–489
Fox J, Shotts K (2009) Delegates or trustees? A theory of political accountability. J Politics 71(4):1225–1237
Frey B (1994) Direct democracy: politico-economic lessons from the Swiss experience. Am Econ Rev 84(2):338–342
Gilles D (1959) Solutions to general non-zero-sum games in contributions to the theory of games IV. In: Tucker A, Luce R (eds) Annals of mathematics and statistics, 40th edn. Princeton University Press, Princeton
Kemeny JG (1959) Mathematics without numbers. Daedalus 88:577–591
Kemeny JG, Snell JL (1962) Mathematical models in the social sciences, chapter 2. MIT Press, Cambridge
Laffond G, Lainé J (2000) Majority voting on orders. Theory Decis 49(3):249–287
Laffond G, Laslier JF, Le Bretton M (1993) The bipartisan set of a tournament game 5(1):182–201
Lainé J, Ozkes A, Sanver M (2015) Working paper. Hyper-stable social welfare functions
Laslier JF (1997) Tournaments solutions and majority voting. Springer, Berlin
Maskin E, Tirole J (2004) The politician and the judge: accountability in government. Am Econ Rev 94(4):1034–1054
Miller NR (1980) A new solution set for tournaments and majority voting: further graph-theoretical approaches to the theory of voting. Am J Political Sci 24(1):68–96
Monroe B (1995) Fully proportional representation. Am Political Sci Rev 89(4):925–940
Potthof R, Brams S (1998) Proportional representation: broadening the options. J Theor Politics 10(2):147–178
Schwartz T (1972) Rationality and the myth of the maximum. Nous 6:97–117
Sen AK, Pattanaik PK (1969) Necessary and sufficient conditions for rational choice under majority decision. J Econ Theory 1:178–202
Shepsle KA, Weingast BR (1984) Uncovered sets and sophisticated voting outcomes with implications for agenda institutions. Am J Political Sci 28(1):49–74
Slater P (1961) Inconsistencies in a schedule of paired comparisons. Biometrica 48:303–312
Tullock G (1967) Towards a mathematics of politics. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor
Acknowledgments
A special thank you to Jerry Green for many helpful conversations about this work. This author also gratefully acknowledges the comments and suggestions of Steven Brams, Lucas Coffman, Drew Fudenberg, Yuichiro Kamada, Klaus Nehring, Alvin Roth, Kenneth Shepsle, Tomasz Strzalecki, William Zwicker, seminar participants at Harvard University, and conference participants at the New York University Graduate Student Political Economy Conference, EconCon 2011, and the Judgment Aggregation and Voting Theory Workshop.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Appendix
Appendix
1.1 Proof for n = 4
In this section, we prove Proposition 3 stated in Sect. 3.2. For \(n=4\), \(UC(T^{\lambda })\) satisfies order consistency.
Proof
Assume majority preferences are consistent with e. We show that there is no ordering that can cover e. The key step is to recognize that we can apply Proposition 1 to rule out any ordering fewer than five transpositions from e: \(eT^{\lambda }\pi \) for any \(\pi \) within two transpositions, so they cannot cover e, and for those three or four transpositions away, even if they beat e, they will be defeated by at least one ordering one or two transpositions from e (which e beats). So, the only orderings that could potentially cover e are five or six transpositions away from e: \(\{a_{4}a_{3}a_{1}a_{2},a_{4}a_{2}a_{3}a_{1},a_{3}a_{4} a_{2}a_{1},a_{4}a_{3}a_{2}a_{1}\} \). We rule these out one at a time:
-
We cannot have \(a_{4}a_{3}a_{1}a_{2}\) covers e, since \(eT^{\lambda } a_{2}a_{3}a_{1}a_{4}T^{\lambda }a_{4}a_{3}a_{1}a_{2}\) for any population with majority preferences consistent with e. Proposition 1 proves \(eT^{\lambda }a_{2}a_{3}a_{1}a_{4}\). We cannot have \(a_{4}a_{3}a_{1}a_{2}T^{\lambda }a_{2}a_{3}a_{1}a_{4}\) since all of the orderings closer or equidistant to \(a_{4}a_{3}a_{1}a_{2}\) than \(a_{2} a_{3}a_{1}a_{4}\) have \(a_{4}\) precedes \(a_{2}\). Thus, if more than half the population were closer to or equidistant to \(a_{4}a_{3}a_{1}a_{2}\), we would not have \(a_{2}\succ a_{4}\) in the majority preference.
-
We cannot have \(a_{4}a_{2}a_{3}a_{1}\) covers e, since we must have \(eT^{\lambda }a_{4}a_{2}a_{3}a_{1}\). All of the orderings closer or equidistant to \(a_{4}a_{3}a_{1}a_{2}\) than e have \(a_{4}\) precedes \(a_{1}\). Thus, if more than half the population were closer to or equidistant to \(a_{4} a_{2}a_{3}a_{1}\) than to e, we would not have \(a_{1}\succ a_{4}\) in the majority preference.
-
We cannot have \(a_{3}a_{4}a_{2}a_{1}\) covers e, since \(eT^{\lambda } a_{1}a_{4}a_{2}a_{3}T^{\lambda }\) \(a_{3}a_{4}a_{2}a_{1}\) for any population with majority preferences consistent with e. Proposition 1 proves \(eT^{\lambda }a_{1}a_{4}a_{2}a_{3}\). We cannot have \(a_{3}a_{4}a_{2}a_{1}T^{\lambda }a_{1}a_{4}a_{2}a_{3}\) since all of the orderings closer or equidistant to \(a_{1}a_{4}a_{2}a_{3}\) than \(a_{3} a_{4}a_{2}a_{1}\) have \(a_{3}\) precedes \(a_{1}\). Thus, if more than half the population were closer to or equidistant to \(a_{3}a_{4}a_{2}a_{1}\), we would not have \(a_{1}\succ a_{3}\) in the majority preference.
-
We cannot have \(a_{4}a_{3}a_{2}a_{1}\) covers e, since \(eT^{\lambda } a_{1}a_{3}a_{2}a_{4}T^{\lambda }a_{4}a_{3}a_{2}a_{1}\) for any population with majority preferences consistent with e. Proposition 1 proves \(eT^{\lambda }a_{1}a_{3}a_{2}a_{4}\). We cannot have \(a_{4}a_{3}a_{2}a_{1}T^{\lambda }a_{1}a_{3}a_{2}a_{4}\) since all of the orderings closer or equidistant to \(a_{4}a_{3}a_{2}a_{1}\) than \(a_{1} a_{3}a_{2}a_{4}\) have \(a_{4}\) precedes \(a_{1}\). Thus, if more than half the population were closer to or equidistant to \(a_{4}a_{3}a_{2}a_{1}\), we would not have \(a_{1}\succ a_{4}\) in the majority preference. \(\square \)
1.2 Population restrictions
A natural question to ask in this context is whether we can impose restrictions on the distribution of preferences that would guarantee order consistency. This domain restriction approach has been adopted by many social choice theorists in attempts to rule out other paradoxical outcomes; perhaps most classic is the single-peakedness restriction pioneered independently by Black (1948) and Arrow (1951) and generalized by Sen and Pattanaik (1969). Their goal was to describe a class of populations for which majority rule over alternatives would not cycle. The domain restriction they proposed requires populations to be unimodal in the sense that all members of the population, for any particular triple of alternatives, must be able to agree on an alternative that is not worst. Assuming the number of voters is odd, this condition is sufficient for transitive majority rule.
Clearly, this restriction will not be enough to assure order consistency, as the class of populations we consider in our counterexample above are indeed single-peaked in terms of preferences over alternatives. However, we can use a similar idea, that of restricting the number of modes in the distribution, in order to derive a sufficient condition for order consistency in our framework. The class of populations with transitive majority rule consistent with the ordering e can be thought of as having a “peak” or cluster of weight around e. Our sufficiency condition says that as we move away from e, we must not encounter another cluster of orderings similar to one another. In order to state this condition more formally, it will be useful to introduce some new terminology. When referring to a population with transitive majority rule consistent with e, we will call any pairwise disagreement with e an error. For example, we will say that an ordering \(\pi \) that is m transpositions from e contains m errors. We can state our sufficiency condition in terms of these errors.
Proposition 5
Consider the class of populations with transitive majority rule consistent with e. Then, order consistency holds if for any set of m errors, \(m\geqq 5\), we have
Proof
Suppose \(e\notin \)
\(UC(T^{\lambda })\). We will show there must exist a set of m errors, \(m\geqq 5\), such that \({\sum } \lambda (\pi |\pi \) contains at least \(\frac{1}{2}\) of these m errors\()>\frac{1}{2}\). Since \(e\notin \)
\(UC(T^{\lambda })\), we know there exists \(\hat{\pi }\) such that \(\hat{\pi }\) covers e. Let \(\hat{\pi }\) contain m errors; we know \(m\geqq 5\) in order for \(\hat{\pi }\) to cover e. Since \(\hat{\pi }\) and e agree on all pairwise choices outside of the m errors, we know that \(f(\pi ,\hat{\pi })\) and \(f(\pi ,e)\) are determined only by how many of the m errors \(\pi \) contains. Those \(\pi \) that have less than \(\frac{1}{2}\) of the m errors have \(f(\pi ,e)<f(\pi ,\hat{\pi })\). So, suppose the set of orderings that had at least \(\frac{1}{2}\) of these m errors in common with \(\hat{\pi }\) had mass less than \(\frac{1}{2}\). Then, we would have \( {\sum } \lambda (\pi |f(\pi ,e)<f(\pi ,\hat{\pi })>\frac{1}{2}\). This would imply \(eT^{\lambda }\hat{\pi }\), contradicting \(\hat{\pi }\) covers e. \(\square \)
This sufficiency condition has a straightforward intuition. If we encounter a population that contains a mass of orderings that are both (a) relatively distant from e, and (b) relatively close to one another, then we may have the type of counterexample presented above. This type of cluster of similar orderings far from e may be able to agree upon a compromise candidate which covers e, but only if together they constitute a majority. The condition rules out this possibility by assuring that no such cluster of mass greater than \(\frac{1}{2}\ \)exists.
This is a sufficient but not necessary condition for order consistency. A gray area exists between the class of populations described in our counterexample above and the class of populations described by this sufficiency condition. For some populations that fail the condition above, the distribution of mass on orderings far from e may be too dispersed to agree upon an ordering like \(\hat{\pi }\) which could beat everything that e beats. One might ask whether we could improve the sufficiency condition by restricting this set of distant orderings to fall within a certain radius of one another. Below, we provide an example that illustrates why this strategy fails.
Example 1
Why Tightening the Sufficiency Condition by Restricting the Radius of the Outlier Orderings Does Not Work.
Consider the following population, a slight variant from the example presented in Sect. 3:
Using the strategy from the proof above, we can show that \(\hat{\pi } =a_{2}a_{1}a_{4}a_{3}a_{6}a_{5}a_{8}a_{7}a_{10}a_{9}\) covers e, the ordering consistent with majority preferences. We need to show that (a) \(\hat{\pi }T^{\lambda }e\) and (b) for all \(\pi ^{\prime }\in \Pi ,\) \(eT^{\lambda }\pi ^{\prime }\Rightarrow \hat{\pi }T^{\lambda }\pi ^{\prime }\). First we will show that \(\hat{\pi }T^{\lambda }e\). For the five orderings in population with weight \(\frac{1}{5}(\frac{1}{2}-\varepsilon ),\) we have \(f(\pi ,\hat{\pi })=1\) and \(f(\pi ,e)=4\). And, we know \(a_{10}a_{9}a_{8}a_{7}a_{6}a_{5}a_{4}a_{3} a_{2}a_{1}\) is closer to \(\hat{\pi }\) than e, since it is maximally distant from e. Thus, \(\frac{1}{2}+2\varepsilon \) of the population is closer to \(\hat{\pi }\) than e, so \(\hat{\pi }T^{\lambda }e.\) Now we need to show there cannot exist \(\pi ^{\prime }\) such that \(eT^{\lambda }\pi ^{\prime }\) but \(\pi ^{\prime }T^{\lambda }\hat{\pi }.\) Suppose there did exist such a \(\pi ^{\prime }\). Then, \(eT^{\lambda }\pi ^{\prime }\) implies that for at least one of the orderings \(\pi \) in population other than e, \(\ f(e,\pi )\le f(\pi ^{\prime },\pi )\). We know there cannot exist a \(\pi ^{\prime }\), \(\pi ^{\prime }\ne e\), such that \(f(e,a_{10}a_{9}a_{8}a_{7}a_{6}a_{5}a_{4} a_{3}a_{2}a_{1})\le f(\pi ^{\prime },a_{10}a_{9}a_{8}a_{7}a_{6}a_{5}a_{4} a_{3}a_{2}a_{1})\). So, it must be that this is true for one of the remaining five orderings. Since for any of these orderings \(f(e,\pi )=4\), we must have \(f(\pi ^{\prime },\pi )\ge 4\) for at least one of those five orderings \(\pi \). And, the fact that \(\pi ^{\prime }T^{\lambda }\hat{\pi }\) implies that we have at least one of the following two cases:
-
1.
For at least one of the orderings with weight \(\frac{1}{5}(\frac{1}{2}-\varepsilon )\), we have \(f(\pi ^{\prime },\pi )\le f(\hat{\pi },\pi )\).
-
2.
For both e and \(a_{10}a_{9}a_{8}a_{7}a_{6}a_{5}a_{4}a_{3}a_{2}a_{1}\), we have \(f(\pi ^{\prime },\pi )<f(\hat{\pi },\pi )\).
For case 1, we know \(f(\hat{\pi },\pi )=1\), so this would imply, \(f(\pi ^{\prime },\pi )\le 1\) for one of the orderings with weight \(\frac{1}{5}(\frac{1}{2}-\varepsilon )\). This leads to the same violation of the triangle inequality that we reached above, since for any two orderings with weight \(\frac{1}{5}(\frac{1}{2}-\varepsilon )\), we have \(f(\pi _{i},\pi _{j})\le 2\). For case 2, \(f(\pi ^{\prime },e)<f(\hat{\pi },e)\) implies \(f(\pi ^{\prime },e)<5.\) And, \(f(\pi ^{\prime },a_{10}a_{9}a_{8}a_{7}a_{6}a_{5}a_{4}a_{3}a_{2}a_{1} )<f(\hat{\pi },a_{10}a_{9}a_{8}a_{7}a_{6}a_{5}a_{4}a_{3}a_{2}a_{1})\) implies \(f(\pi ^{\prime },a_{10}a_{9}a_{8}a_{7}a_{6}a_{5}a_{4}a_{3}a_{2}a_{1})<40\). But, \(f(\pi ^{\prime },e)<5\) and \(f(\pi ^{\prime },a_{10}a_{9}a_{8}a_{7}a_{6}a_{5} a_{4}a_{3}a_{2}a_{1})<40\) cannot both hold, since the first implies \(\pi ^{\prime }\) has fewer than five errors and the second implies it has more than five errors. This leads to a contradiction. Thus, order consistency fails for this population.
This example illustrates the difficulty we encounter if we attempt to tighten the sufficiency condition for ordering consistency by imposing a radius around the orderings with common errors. Taking the basic counterexample from above, where the minority orderings all lie relatively close to another, we can move some weight to \(a_{10}a_{9}a_{8}a_{7}a_{6}a_{5}a_{4}a_{3}a_{2}a_{1}\) and still arrive at \(\hat{\pi }\) covers e. Thus, it is not always true that we need the minority orderings to be relatively close to one another in order to have order consistency fail.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Coffman, K.B. Representative democracy and the implementation of majority-preferred alternatives. Soc Choice Welf 46, 477–494 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-015-0922-3
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-015-0922-3