[go: up one dir, main page]
More Web Proxy on the site http://driver.im/ Skip to main content
Log in

Extensions of the Simpson voting rule to the committee selection setting

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Committee selection rules are procedures selecting sets of candidates (committees) of a given size on the basis of the preferences of the voters. Two natural extensions of the well-known single-winner Simpson voting rule to the multiwinner setting have been identified in the literature. We propose an in-depth analysis of those committee selection rules, assessing and comparing them with respect to several desirable properties, among which are unanimity, fixed majority, non-imposition, stability, local stability, Condorcet consistency, some kinds of monotonicity, resolvability and consensus committee. We also investigate the probability that the two methods are resolute and suffer the reversal bias, the Condorcet loser paradox and the leaving member paradox. We compare the results obtained with the ones related to further well-known committee selection rules. The probability assumption on which our results are based is the widely used Impartial Anonymous Culture.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
£29.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price includes VAT (United Kingdom)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The Simpson voting rule also is known as the Simpson–Kramer, the Condorcet and the Minimax voting rule (see Kramer 1977; Simpson 1969).

  2. Obviously, the concept is a generalization to the committee selection setting of the well-known concept of weak Condorcet winner.

  3. In Coelho (2004) \(\mathfrak {M}\) is denoted by SEO and it is defined as

    $$\begin{aligned} \mathfrak {M}(C,V,p,k)=\underset{W\in 2_{k}^{C}}{\mathrm {arg\,min}}\,\max _{y\not \in W,x\in W}c_{p}(y,x). \end{aligned}$$
  4. Those properties largely are studied in the literature in the setting of voting rules. See, for instance, Bubboloni and Gori (2016), Diss and Gehrlein (2012), Diss and Tlidi (2018), Duggan and Schwartz (2000), Fishburn and Gehrlein (1976), Gehrlein and Lepelley (2010), Jeong and Ju (2017) and Saari and Barney (2003). In the committee selection setting, resoluteness and immunity to the reversal bias are studied in Bubboloni and Gori (2019) for a fixed number of voters and alternatives; the Condorcet loser paradox is introduced here for the first time.

  5. See, for instance, Diss and Doghmi (2016), Kamwa and Merlin (2015) and Staring (1986).

  6. Note that if k were allowed to be 1, then every csr would suffer the leaving member paradox.

  7. Note that when, \(m\le 2\) or \(n=1\), the analysis of the considered properties turns out to be straightforward.

  8. See Diss and Doghmi (2016) and Elkind et al. (2017) for the definitions of the csrs.

  9. For a detailed description of algorithms computing Ehrhart polynomials, we recommend the report by Verdoolaege et al. (2005).

  10. Possible for all of the scoring csrs we are considering here but, unfortunately, that is not true when we consider \(\mathfrak {S}\) and \(\mathfrak {M}\). For those csrs exact probabilities can be obtained only for \(n\in \{2,3,4,5\}\).

  11. The MATLAB code of our simulations is available upon request.

  12. Once again the technique cannot be used for \(\mathfrak {S}\) and \(\mathfrak {M}\) for which obtaining the probabilities in the limiting case is possible only with computer simulations. We consider for them a number of voters \(n=100{,}000\).

  13. This is another assumption widely used for analyzing the probability of electoral events. Under this assumption, the preference relation of each voter is drawn uniformly at random from the set of all possible linear orders.

References

  • Aziz, H., Elkind, E., Faliszewski, P., Lackner, M., & Skowron, P. (2017). The condorcet principle for multiwinner election: from short listing to proportionality. In Proceedings of the twenty-sixth international joint conference on artificial intelligence (IJCAI-17), pp. 84–90.

  • Barberà, S., & Coelho, D. (2008). How to choose a non-controversial list with \(k\) names. Social Choice and Welfare, 31, 79–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bubboloni, D., & Gori, M. (2016). On the reversal bias of the Minimax social choice correspondence. Mathematical Social Sciences, 81, 53–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bubboloni, D., & Gori, M. (2019). Breaking ties in collective decision making. arXiv:1706.10165v4.

  • Bruns, W., Ichim, B., Römer, T., Sieg, R., & Söger, C. (2017). Normaliz: Algorithms for rational cones and affine monoids. http://normaliz.uos.de.

  • Bruns, W., Ichim, B., & Söger, C. (2019). Computations of volumes and Ehrhart series in four candidates elections. Annals of Operations Research,. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10479-019-03152-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cervone, D., Gehrlein, W. V., & Zwicker, W. (2005). Which scoring rule maximizes Condorcet efficiency under IAC? Theory and Decision, 58, 145–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coelho, D. (2004). Understanding, evaluating and selecting voting rules through games and axioms (Ph.d. thesis), Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona, Departament d’Economia i d’Història Econòmica. Available at http://hdl.handle.net/10803/4056.

  • Courtin, S., Martin, M., & Moyouwou, I. (2015). The \(q\)-majority efficiency of positional rules. Theory and Decision, 79, 31–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diss, M. (2015). Strategic manipulability of self-selective social choice rules. Annals of Operations Research, 229, 347–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diss, M., & Doghmi, A. (2016). Multi-winner scoring election methods: Condorcet consistency and paradoxes. Public Choice, 169, 97–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diss, M., & Gehrlein, W. V. (2012). Borda’s paradox with weighted scoring rules. Social Choice and Welfare, 38, 121–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diss, M., & Gehrlein, W. V. (2015). The true impact of voting rule selection on Condorcet efficiency. Economics Bulletin, 35, 2418–2426.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diss, M., Louichi, A., Merlin, V., & Smaoui, H. (2012). An example of probability computations under the IAC assumption: The stability of scoring rules. Mathematical Social Sciences, 64, 57–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diss, M., & Tlidi, A. (2018). Another perspective on Borda’s paradox. Theory and Decision, 84(1), 99–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duggan, J., & Schwartz, T. (2000). Strategic manipulability without resoluteness or shared beliefs: Gibbard-Satterthwaite generalized. Social Choice and Welfare, 17(1), 85–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elkind, E., Faliszewski, P., Skowron, P., & Slinko, A. (2017). Properties of multiwinner voting rules. Social Choice and Welfare, 48(3), 599–632.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C., & Gehrlein, W. V. (1976). Borda’s rule, positional voting, and Condorcet’s simple majority principle. Public Choice, 28, 79–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franz, M. (2017). Convex - a Maple package for convex geometry, version 1.2. http://www-home.math.uwo.ca/~mfranz/convex/.

  • Gehrlein, W. V. (1985). The Condorcet criterion and committee selection. Mathematical Social Sciences, 10, 199–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V., & Fishburn, P. C. (1976). The probability of the paradox of voting: A computable solution. Journal of Economic Theory, 13, 14–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V., & Lepelley, D. (2010). On the probability of observing Borda’s paradox. Social Choice and Welfare, 35, 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V., & Lepelley, D. (2011). Voting paradoxes and group coherence. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V., & Lepelley, D. (2017). Elections, voting rules and paradoxical outcomes. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V., Lepelley, D., & Plassmann, F. (2018). An evaluation of the benefit of using two-stage election procedures. Homo Oeconomicus, 35(1–2), 53–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V., Lepelley, D., & Moyouwou, I. (2016). A note on approval voting and electing the Condorcet loser. Mathematical Social Sciences, 80, 115–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V., Lepelley, D., & Moyouwou, I. (2015). Voters’ preference diversity, concepts of agreement and Condorcet’s paradox. Quality and Quantity, 49(6), 2345–2368.

    Google Scholar 

  • González-Díaz, J., Hendrickx, R., & Lohmann, E. (2014). Paired comparisons analysis: an axiomatic approach of ranking methods. Social Choice and Welfare, 42, 139–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeong, H., & Ju, B. G. (2017). Resolute majority rules. Theory and Decision, 82, 31–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamwa, E. (2017a). On stable rules for selecting committees. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 70, 36–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamwa, E. (2017b). Stable rules for electing committees and divergence on outcomes. Group Decision and Negotiation, 26, 547–564.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamwa, E., & Merlin, V. (2015). Scoring rules over subsets of alternatives: Consistency and paradoxes. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 61, 130–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamwa, E., & Valognes, F. (2017). Scoring rules and preference restrictions: The strong Borda paradox revisited. Revue d’Economie Politique, 127(3), 375–395.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, G. H. (1977). A dynamical model of political equilibrium. Journal of Economic Theory, 16, 310–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepelley, D., Moyouwou, I., & Smaoui, H. (2018). Monotonicity paradoxes in three-candidate elections using scoring elimination rules. Social Choice and Welfare, 50(1), 1–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepelley, D., Louichi, A., & Smaoui, H. (2008). On Ehrhart polynomials and probability calculations in voting theory. Social Choice and Welfare, 30, 363–383.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moyouwou, I., & Tchantcho, H. (2017). Asymptotic vulnerability of positional voting rules to coalitional manipulation. Mathematical Social Sciences, 89, 70–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moulin, H. (1988). Axioms of cooperative decision making. Cambridge: Cambridge Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G., & Barney, S. (2003). Consequences of reversing preferences. The Mathematical Intelligencer, 25, 17–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulze, M. (2011). A new monotonic, clone-independent, reversal symmetric, and Condorcet-consistent single-winner election method. Social Choice and Welfare, 36, 267–303.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, P. B. (1969). On defining areas of voter choice: Professor Tullock on stable voting. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 83, 478–490.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smaoui, H., Lepelley, D., & Moyouwou, I. (2016). Borda elimination rule and monotonicity paradoxes in three-candidate elections. Economics Bulletin, 36(3), 1722–1728.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staring, M. (1986). Two paradoxes of committee elections. Mathematics Magazine, 59, 158–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tideman, N. (1987). Independence of clones as a criterion for voting rules. Social Choice and Welfare, 4, 185–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tideman, N. (2006). Collective decisions and voting: The potential for public choice. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verdoolaege, S., Woods, K. M., Bruynooghe, M., & Cools, R. (2005). Computation and manipulation of enumerators of integer projections of parametric polytopes. Technical Report CW 392, Katholieke Universiteit Leuven.

  • Wilson, M. C., & Pritchard, G. (2007). Probability calculations under the IAC hypothesis. Mathematical Social Sciences, 54, 244–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, H. P. (1975). Social choice scoring functions. SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics, 28(4), 824–838.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors thank two anonymous reviewers and the editor for their valuable comments and suggestions. Daniela Bubboloni was partially supported by Gruppo Nazionale per le Strutture Algebriche, Geometriche e le loro Applicazioni (GNSAGA) of Istituto Nazionale di Alta Matematica (INdAM). Mostapha Diss gratefully acknowledges the financial support of Initiative D’EXcellence (IDEXLYON) from Université de Lyon (project INDEPTH) within the Programme Investissements d’Avenir (ANR-16-IDEX-0005).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mostapha Diss.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary material 1 (pdf 164 KB)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bubboloni, D., Diss, M. & Gori, M. Extensions of the Simpson voting rule to the committee selection setting. Public Choice 183, 151–185 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00692-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00692-6

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation