[go: up one dir, main page]
More Web Proxy on the site http://driver.im/Jump to content

Dedekind cut

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Dedekind used his cut to construct the irrational, real numbers.

In mathematics, Dedekind cuts, named after German mathematician Richard Dedekind (but previously considered by Joseph Bertrand[1][2]), are а method of construction of the real numbers from the rational numbers. A Dedekind cut is a partition of the rational numbers into two sets A and B, such that each element of A is less than every element of B, and A contains no greatest element. The set B may or may not have a smallest element among the rationals. If B has a smallest element among the rationals, the cut corresponds to that rational. Otherwise, that cut defines a unique irrational number which, loosely speaking, fills the "gap" between A and B.[3] In other words, A contains every rational number less than the cut, and B contains every rational number greater than or equal to the cut. An irrational cut is equated to an irrational number which is in neither set. Every real number, rational or not, is equated to one and only one cut of rationals.[3]

Dedekind cuts can be generalized from the rational numbers to any totally ordered set by defining a Dedekind cut as a partition of a totally ordered set into two non-empty parts A and B, such that A is closed downwards (meaning that for all a in A, xa implies that x is in A as well) and B is closed upwards, and A contains no greatest element. See also completeness (order theory).

It is straightforward to show that a Dedekind cut among the real numbers is uniquely defined by the corresponding cut among the rational numbers. Similarly, every cut of reals is identical to the cut produced by a specific real number (which can be identified as the smallest element of the B set). In other words, the number line where every real number is defined as a Dedekind cut of rationals is a complete continuum without any further gaps.

Definition

[edit]

A Dedekind cut is a partition of the rationals into two subsets and such that

  1. is nonempty.
  2. (equivalently, is nonempty).
  3. If , , and , then . ( is "closed downwards".)
  4. If , then there exists a such that . ( does not contain a greatest element.)

By omitting the first two requirements, we formally obtain the extended real number line.

Representations

[edit]

It is more symmetrical to use the (A, B) notation for Dedekind cuts, but each of A and B does determine the other. It can be a simplification, in terms of notation if nothing more, to concentrate on one "half" — say, the lower one — and call any downward-closed set A without greatest element a "Dedekind cut".

If the ordered set S is complete, then, for every Dedekind cut (A, B) of S, the set B must have a minimal element b, hence we must have that A is the interval (−∞, b), and B the interval [b, +∞). In this case, we say that b is represented by the cut (A, B).

The important purpose of the Dedekind cut is to work with number sets that are not complete. The cut itself can represent a number not in the original collection of numbers (most often rational numbers). The cut can represent a number b, even though the numbers contained in the two sets A and B do not actually include the number b that their cut represents.

For example if A and B only contain rational numbers, they can still be cut at by putting every negative rational number in A, along with every non-negative rational number whose square is less than 2; similarly B would contain every positive rational number whose square is greater than or equal to 2. Even though there is no rational value for , if the rational numbers are partitioned into A and B this way, the partition itself represents an irrational number.

Ordering of cuts

[edit]

Regard one Dedekind cut (A, B) as less than another Dedekind cut (C, D) (of the same superset) if A is a proper subset of C. Equivalently, if D is a proper subset of B, the cut (A, B) is again less than (C, D). In this way, set inclusion can be used to represent the ordering of numbers, and all other relations (greater than, less than or equal to, equal to, and so on) can be similarly created from set relations.

The set of all Dedekind cuts is itself a linearly ordered set (of sets). Moreover, the set of Dedekind cuts has the least-upper-bound property, i.e., every nonempty subset of it that has any upper bound has a least upper bound. Thus, constructing the set of Dedekind cuts serves the purpose of embedding the original ordered set S, which might not have had the least-upper-bound property, within a (usually larger) linearly ordered set that does have this useful property.

Construction of the real numbers

[edit]

A typical Dedekind cut of the rational numbers is given by the partition with

[4]

This cut represents the irrational number in Dedekind's construction. The essential idea is that we use a set , which is the set of all rational numbers whose squares are less than 2, to "represent" number , and further, by defining properly arithmetic operators over these sets (addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division), these sets (together with these arithmetic operations) form the familiar real numbers.

To establish this, one must show that really is a cut (according to the definition) and the square of , that is (please refer to the link above for the precise definition of how the multiplication of cuts is defined), is (note that rigorously speaking this number 2 is represented by a cut ). To show the first part, we show that for any positive rational with , there is a rational with and . The choice works, thus is indeed a cut. Now armed with the multiplication between cuts, it is easy to check that (essentially, this is because ). Therefore to show that , we show that , and it suffices to show that for any , there exists , . For this we notice that if , then for the constructed above, this means that we have a sequence in whose square can become arbitrarily close to , which finishes the proof.

Note that the equality b2 = 2 cannot hold since is not rational.

Relation to interval arithmetic

[edit]

Given a Dedekind cut representing the real number by splitting the rationals into where rationals in are less than and rationals in are greater than , it can be equivalently represented as the set of pairs with and , with the lower cut and the upper cut being given by projections. This corresponds exactly to the set of intervals approximating .

This allows the basic arithmetic operations on the real numbers to be defined in terms of interval arithmetic. This property and its relation with real numbers given only in terms of and is particularly important in weaker foundations such as constructive analysis.

Generalizations

[edit]

Arbitrary linearly ordered sets

[edit]

In the general case of an arbitrary linearly ordered set X, a cut is a pair such that and , imply . Some authors add the requirement that both A and B are nonempty.[5]

If neither A has a maximum, nor B has a minimum, the cut is called a gap. A linearly ordered set endowed with the order topology is compact if and only if it has no gap.[6]

Surreal numbers

[edit]

A construction resembling Dedekind cuts is used for (one among many possible) constructions of surreal numbers. The relevant notion in this case is a Cuesta-Dutari cut,[7] named after the Spanish mathematician Norberto Cuesta Dutari [es].

Partially ordered sets

[edit]

More generally, if S is a partially ordered set, a completion of S means a complete lattice L with an order-embedding of S into L. The notion of complete lattice generalizes the least-upper-bound property of the reals.

One completion of S is the set of its downwardly closed subsets, ordered by inclusion. A related completion that preserves all existing sups and infs of S is obtained by the following construction: For each subset A of S, let Au denote the set of upper bounds of A, and let Al denote the set of lower bounds of A. (These operators form a Galois connection.) Then the Dedekind–MacNeille completion of S consists of all subsets A for which (Au)l = A; it is ordered by inclusion. The Dedekind-MacNeille completion is the smallest complete lattice with S embedded in it.

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ Bertrand, Joseph (1849). Traité d'Arithmétique. page 203. An incommensurable number can be defined only by indicating how the magnitude it expresses can be formed by means of unity. In what follows, we suppose that this definition consists of indicating which are the commensurable numbers smaller or larger than it ....
  2. ^ Spalt, Detlef (2019). Eine kurze Geschichte der Analysis. Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-57816-2. ISBN 978-3-662-57815-5.
  3. ^ a b Dedekind, Richard (1872). Continuity and Irrational Numbers (PDF). Section IV. Whenever, then, we have to do with a cut produced by no rational number, we create a new irrational number, which we regard as completely defined by this cut ... . From now on, therefore, to every definite cut there corresponds a definite rational or irrational number ....
  4. ^ In the second line, may be replaced by without any difference as there is no solution for in and is already forbidden by the first condition. This results in the equivalent expression
  5. ^ R. Engelking, General Topology, I.3
  6. ^ Jun-Iti Nagata, Modern General Topology, Second revised edition, Theorem VIII.2, p. 461. Actually, the theorem holds in the setting of generalized ordered spaces, but in this more general setting pseudo-gaps should be taken into account.
  7. ^ Alling, Norman L. (1987). Foundations of Analysis over Surreal Number Fields. Mathematics Studies 141. North-Holland. ISBN 0-444-70226-1.

References

[edit]
  • Dedekind, Richard, Essays on the Theory of Numbers, "Continuity and Irrational Numbers," Dover Publications: New York, ISBN 0-486-21010-3. Also available at Project Gutenberg.
[edit]