Abstract
In the paper, we apply Kooi and Tamminga’s correspondence analysis (that has been previously applied to some notable three- and four-valued logics) to some conventional and functionally incomplete fragments of classical propositional logic. In particular, the paper deals with the implication, disjunction, and negation fragments. Additionally, we consider an application of correspondence analysis to some connectiveless fragment with certain basic properties of the logical consequence relation only. As a result of the application, one obtains a sound and complete natural deduction system for any binary extension of each fragment in question. With the focus on exclusive disjunction we comparatively study the proposed systems. Finally, we discuss Segerberg’s systems for connectiveless and negation fragments and compare them with our systems.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
We come back to this issue in Sect. 5, where we compare Segerberg’s approach and ours, since Segerberg, as we did, considered classical logic. Let us notice that Kooi and Tamminga do not mention Segerberg’s work.
For the purpose of this paper, we don’t treat conjunction (\( \wedge \)) as a primitive. However, correspondence analysis works with conjunction, too.
Note case \( f_\circ (0,0)=1 \) below clearly indicates some extensions contain tautologies that isn’t the case for the other correspondence analyses in this paper. It doesn’t imply they don’t contain tautologies (in fact, they do, e.g. the implication fragment contains Peirce’s law; see Sect. 3.1 below). However, correspondence analysis for the disjunction fragment shows the existence of tautologies in some of its extensions explicitely.
The reader will find some similarities with Kalmár’s folklore conditions in the equivalences below. However, the difference is that Kalmár’s conditions are usually expressed via some implicational formulae (see, for example, [17]).
The rule (EEM) is inspired by a formula \( A\vee (A\rightarrow B) \) (see Definition 4.4 which will clarify it) to have been known as the extended law of excluded middle [19, p. 17]. Note by adding \( A\vee (A\rightarrow B) \) or Peirce’s law \( ((A\rightarrow B)\rightarrow A)\rightarrow A \) to intuitionistic logic one obtains classical logic [19, p. 18]. To be sure, there are other formulae which give the same result (for example, it is a folklore about the law of double negation elimination \( \lnot \lnot A\rightarrow A \) and the law of excluded middle \( A\vee \lnot A \)). We stress, however, that despite some laws discussed in this footnote contain disjunction or negation the rules of the natural deduction system for the implication fragment contain implication only.
Though the symbol \( \veebar \) isn’t in the languages of this paper, we will use it for the human-friendliness of the presentation.
This example is a kind of introduction rule for exclusive disjunction and may be viewed as an analogue of one of the well-known introduction rules for inclusive disjunction: \(\frac{p}{p\vee q}\).
To be sure, there are deductively equal alternatives to these rules. We pick up this pair of rules as the most convenient for our completeness proof. The rule (EM) is inspired by the law of excluded middle \( A\vee \lnot A\) (see Definition 4.3 which will clarify it) and the rule (EFQ) is Ex Falso Quodlibet.
Note we adapt this Definition to the rule of extended excluded middle (EEM) while Definition 4.3 is adapted to the rule of excluded middle (EM). Since non-trivial theories which are defined in Definition 4.3 are called maximal ones, so non-trivial theories which are defined in Definition 4.4 are said to be extended maximal ones.
We acknowledge, however, that in [8] the authors do not claim that Segerberg’s ideas could not be extended to n-valued logic without their reduction.
References
Asenjo, F.G.: A calculus of antinomies. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic 7, 103–105 (1966)
Avron, A.: Natural 3-valued logics—characterization and proof theory. J. Symbol. Logic 56, 276–294 (1991)
Belnap, N.D.: A useful four-valued logic. In: Dunn, J.M., Epstein, G. (eds.) Modern Uses of Multiple-Valued Logic, pp. 7–37. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht (1977)
Belnap, N.D.: How a computer should think. In: Rule, G. (ed.) Contemporary Aspects of Philosophy, pp. 30–56. Oriel Press, Mumbai (1977)
Bolotov, A., Bocharov, V., Gorchakov, A., Shangin, V.: Automated first order natural deduction. In: Proceedings of the 2nd Indian International Conference on Artificial Intelligence, pp. 1292–1311 (2015)
Caleiro, C., Marcos, J.: Classic-like analytic tableaux for finite-valued logics. In: WoLLIC-2009, Selected Papers, Ed. by H. Ono, R. de Queiroz, M. Kanazawa. Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence. 5514, Springer pp. 268–280 (2009)
Copi, I.M., Cohen, C., McMahon, K.: Introduction to logic, 14th edn. Routledge, Abingdon-on-Thames (2011)
Englander, C., Haeusler, E.H., Pereira, L.C.: Finitely many-valued logics and natural deduction. Logic J. IGPL 22(2), 333–354 (2013)
Dunn, J.M.: Intuitive semantics for first-degree entailment and coupled trees. Philos. Stud. 29, 149–168 (1976)
Heyting, A.: Die Formalen Regeln der intuitionistischen Logik. Sitzungsber. Preussischen Acad. Wiss. Berlin, pp. 42–46 (1930)
Ferrari, M., Fiorentini, C.: Proof-Search in natural deduction calculus for classical propositional logic. Lecture Notes in Comput. Sci. 9323, 237–252 (2015)
Karpenko, A., Tomova, N.: Bochvar’s three-valued logic and literal paralogics: their lattice and functional equivalence. Logic Log. Philos. 26(2), 207–235 (2017)
Kleene, S.C.: On a notation for ordinal numbers. J. Symbol. Logic 3, 150–155 (1938)
Kooi, B., Tamminga, A.: Completeness via correspondence for extensions of the logic of paradox. Rev. Symbol. Logic 5, 720–730 (2012)
Leszczyńska-Jasion, D., Petrukhin, Y., Shangin, V., Jukiewicz, M.: Functional completeness in CPL via correspondence analysis. Bull. Sect. Logic 48(1), 45–76 (2019)
Leszczyńska-Jasion, D., Petrukhin, Y., Shangin, V.: The method of Socratic proofs meets correspondence analysis. Bull. Sect. Logic 48(2), 99–116 (2019)
Mendelson, E.: Introduction to Mathematical Logic, 4th edn. Chapman & Hall, Boca Raton (1997)
Negri, S., von Plato, J.: Structural Proof-Theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2001)
Odintsov, S.P.: Constructive Negations and Paraconsistency. Springer, Berlin (2008)
Osorio, M., Carballido, J.L.: Brief study of \({ G}_3^\prime \) logic. J. Appl. Non-Class. Logic 18(4), 475–499 (2008)
Petrukhin, Y., Shangin, V.: Automated correspondence analysis for the binary extensions of the logic of paradox. Rev. Symbol. Logic 10(4), 756–781 (2017)
Petrukhin, Y., Shangin, V.: Natural three-valued logics characterised by natural deduction. Log. et Anal. 61(244), 407–427 (2018)
Petrukhin, Y., Shangin, V.: Automated proof-searching for strong Kleene logic and its binary extensions via correspondence analysis. Log. Log. Philos. 28(2), 223–257 (2019)
Petrukhin, Y., Shangin, V.: Correspondence analysis and automated proof-searching for first degree entailment. Eur. J. Math. 6(4), 1452–1495 (2020)
Petrukhin, Y.: Generalized correspondence analysis for three-valued logics. Log. Univers. 12(3–4), 423–460 (2018)
Priest, G.: The logic of paradox. J. Philos. Logic 8, 219–241 (1979)
Segerberg, K.: Arbitrary truth-value functions and natural deduction. Math. Logic Quart. 29(11), 557–564 (1983)
Shangin, V.O.: A precise definition of an inference (by the example of natural deduction systems for logics \( I_{\langle \alpha ,\beta \rangle } \)). Log. Investig. 23(1), 83–104 (2017)
Tamminga, A.: Correspondence analysis for strong three-valued logic. Log. Investig. 20, 255–268 (2014)
Tomova, N.E.: A lattice of implicative extensions of regular Kleene’s logics. Rep. Math. Logic 47, 173–182 (2012)
Acknowledgements
We would like to thank the first reviewer for the valuable suggestions. The second author thanks Xenia Shliakhtina for the everlasting inspiration.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
The first author is supported by Polish National Science Centre, Grant Number DEC-2017/25/B/HS1/01268. The second author is supported by RFBR, Grant Number 20-011-00698 A.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Petrukhin, Y., Shangin, V. Correspondence Analysis for Some Fragments of Classical Propositional Logic. Log. Univers. 15, 67–85 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-021-00267-4
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-021-00267-4
Keywords
- Classical logic
- Correspondence analysis
- Disjunction fragment
- Implication fragment
- Negation fragment
- Natural deduction