Abstract
This paper explores the question of what makes diagrammatic representations effective for human logical reasoning, focusing on how Euler diagrams support syllogistic reasoning. It is widely held that diagrammatic representations aid intuitive understanding of logical reasoning. In the psychological literature, however, it is still controversial whether and how Euler diagrams can aid untrained people to successfully conduct logical reasoning such as set-theoretic and syllogistic reasoning. To challenge the negative view, we build on the findings of modern diagrammatic logic and introduce an Euler-style diagrammatic representation system that is designed to avoid problems inherent to a traditional version of Euler diagrams. It is hypothesized that Euler diagrams are effective not only in interpreting sentential premises but also in reasoning about semantic structures implicit in given sentences. To test the hypothesis, we compared Euler diagrams with other types of diagrams having different syntactic or semantic properties. Experiment compared the difference in performance between syllogistic reasoning with Euler diagrams and Venn diagrams. Additional analysis examined the case of a linear variant of Euler diagrams, in which set-relationships are represented by one-dimensional lines. The experimental results provide evidence supporting our hypothesis. It is argued that the efficacy of diagrams in supporting syllogistic reasoning crucially depends on the way they represent the relational information contained in categorical sentences.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
Bauer and Johnson-Laird (personal communication) in their unpublished study also reported that while Euler diagrams—or, more specifically, what we will classify as a traditional form of Euler diagrams (Euler circles)—improved reasoning with a class of difficult syllogisms but retarded reasoning with a class of easy syllogisms.
It is standard in the literature of diagrammatic logic to distinguish between two layers of diagrammatic syntax: concrete (token) syntax and abstract (type) syntax (Howse et al. 2002). The former is concerned with the surface structure of a diagram that is visible to users, while the latter gives a formal definition that concrete diagrams must obey. Since we are concerned with cognitive properties of concrete diagrams presented to users, by (diagrammatic) syntax we mean concrete syntax throughout this paper. This is consistent with Stenning and Lemon’s (2001) cognitive view. They claimed that a concatenation is self-evident in a diagrammatic representation, and thus semantic information can be directly interpreted from a diagrammatic representation without the mediation of abstract syntax.
Euler invented his diagrams to teach Aristotelian syllogistic logic to a German princess. Indeed, the origin of such diagrams may go back still further. According to Baron’s (1969) historical review, we can find the original idea at least in the thirteenth century scholar Ramon Lull (1617). Furthermore, in Leibniz’s (1903/1988) work in the seventeenth century, there is the description of the use of diagrams to represent syllogisms although it was only much later that his work was published.
Here, “Euler” diagrams refers to diagrams based on topological relations, such as inclusion and exclusion relations, between circles. Thus, both diagrams in Gergonne’s system and those in our EUL system are instances of Euler diagrams, whereas Venn diagrams are not. In fact, the Euler diagrams currently studied in diagrammatic logic are typically based on the Existence-Free Assumption for minimal regions (EFA) rather than the type used in Gergonne’s system (cf. Stapleton 2005).
Linear diagrams for categorical syllogisms were introduced by Leibniz (1903/1988) in the seventeenth century (cf. Politzer et al. 2006). In the later eras, the linear diagrams were developed by the work of Lambert (1764). More recently, Englebretsen (1992) provided a logical system of deductive inference with linear diagrams with two-dimensional spaces. Although it is known that Englebretsen’s diagrams are unable to express complex logical inferences and hence have limited expressive power (cf. Lemon and Pratt 1998), linear diagrams are generally expressive enough to represent basic categorical syllogisms.
The EUL system can derive not only simple syllogisms with two premises but also a chain of syllogisms with more than two premises (the so-called sorites).
It is noted that this process of checking the invalidity of inferences is similar to the one known as “negation as failure” in the AI literature. One can see that the role of diagrams is to limit the possible search space of drawable conclusions.
The relevant constraint on unification, called the constraint (3), is the following: for any circles X, Y and Z, if neither inclusion or exclusion relation holds between X and Y in the combined diagram, put X and Y in such a way that X and Y are partially overlapped each other.
This classification of one/multiple model syllogisms is different from one in the mental model theory. In contrast to this study, for example, Bucciarelli and Johnson-Laird (1999) classified the AI1 syllogism having the premises All B are A and Some C are B to a single model syllogism.
We used the following translation: “Subete no A wa B de aru” for All A are B, “Dono A mo B de nai” for No A are B, “Aru A wa B de aru” for Some A are B, “Aru A wa B de nai” for Some A are not B. Here we use the quantifiers “subete” and “dono” for all, and “aru” for some. One remarkable difference between English and Japanese is in the translation of No A are B. Since in Japanese there is no negative quantifier corresponding to No, we use the translation “Dono A mo B de nai”, which literally means All A is not B. Except this point, we see no essential differences between English and Japanese. So we will refer to English translation in this paper.
They were regarded as the participants who gave up halfway and dropped out.
Here our instruction emphasized that the meaning of categorical sentences used in our experiment does not contain the existential import. Concretely, the following is given: All A are B does not imply that there are some objects which are A; thus, All A are B does not imply Some A are B. Similarly, No A are B does not imply that there are some objects which are A. Thus, No A are B does not imply Some A are not B.
The accuracy rate for those tasks which have more than one correct answer is described as “X/Y % (Z %)”, where X % represents the accuracy rate for the first correct answer, Y % the second, and Z % the rate for those who selected both correct answers.
Our result is consistent with those presented in Chapman et al. (2014), where the ease of comprehension of Linear, Euler and Venn diagrams was examined. Sato et al. (2011) also reported a similar result on the information extraction from Euler and Venn diagrams. Their empirical results suggested that the interpretation of Venn diagrams requires more substantial efforts than that of Euler diagrams.
In our Experiment, the participants in the Venn group were provided with diagrams consisting of two circles that corresponded to the premises of a given syllogism. However, we also tested a situation where participants are initially provided with Venn diagrams consisting of three circles, or “3-Venn diagrams”, namely \(D_3\) and \(D_4\) of Fig. 12. With 3-Venn diagrams, participants could skip the first steps of adding new circles; the only step needed is to superpose the two premise diagrams. Thus, it may be predicted that 3-Venn diagrams are relatively easy to manipulate in syllogism solving, even for novices. In fact, in the experiments of Sato et al. (2010), we obtained results confirming this prediction.
Further evidence that diagrammatic reasoning has features inherent to System 2 comes from the fact that it can be faster than linguistic or sentential reasoning. Several experiments examined the solution time for reasoning tasks with diagrams and reported that it was short than that for reasoning tasks without diagrams; see Bauer and Johnson-Laird (1993), Cheng (2004), Sato et al. (2015).
References
Alter, A. L., Oppenheimer, D. M., Epley, N., & Eyre, R. N. (2007). Overcoming intuition: Metacognitive difficulty activates analytic reasoning. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 136, 569–576.
Baron, M. E. (1969). A note on the historical development of logic diagrams: Leibniz, Euler and Venn. The Mathematical Gazette, 53, 113–125.
Barwise, J., & Cooper, R. (1981). Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 4, 159–219.
Barwise, J., & Etchemendy, J. (1991/1996). Visual information and valid reasoning. In W. Zimmerman & S. Cunningham (Eds.), Visualization in teaching and learning mathematics, MAA Notes, Number 19 (pp. 9–24). Reprinted in G. Allwein & J. Barwise (Eds). (1996). Logical reasoning with diagrams (pp. 3–26). New York: Oxford University Press.
Barwise, J., & Etchemendy, J. (1994). Hyperproof, CSLI Lecture Notes, No. 42. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.
Barwise, J., & Hammer, E. (1996). Diagrams and the concept of logical system. In G. Allwein & J. Barwise (Eds.), Logical reasoning with diagrams (pp. 49–78). New York: Oxford University Press.
Bauer, M., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1993). How diagrams can improve reasoning. Psychological Science, 4, 372–378.
Benoy, F., & Rodgers, P. (2007). Evaluating the comprehension of Euler diagrams. In E. Banissi, et al. (Eds.), Proceedings of information visualization 2007 (pp. 771–778). Los Alamitos, CA: IEEE Computer Society.
Blackburn, P., & Bos, J. (2005). Representation and inference for natural language: A first course in computational semantics. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.
Boolos, G. (1984). On ‘syllogistic inference’. Cognition, 17, 181–182.
Bucciarelli, M., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1999). Strategies in syllogistic reasoning. Cognitive Science, 23, 247–303.
Calvillo, D. P., DeLeeuw, K., & Revlin, R. (2006). Deduction with Euler circles: Diagrams that hurt. In D. Baker-Plummer, R. Cox, & N. Swoboda (Eds.), Proceedings of Diagrams 2006, LNAI 4045 (pp. 199–203). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.
Camp, E. (2007). Thinking with maps. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 145–182.
Chapman, L., & Chapman, J. (1959). Atmosphere effect re-examined. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 58, 220–226.
Chapman, P., Stapleton, G., Rodgers, P., Micallef, L., & Blake, A. (2014). Visualizing sets: An empirical comparison of diagram types. In T. Dwyer, H. Purchase, & A. Delaney (Eds.), Proceedings of Diagrams 2014, LNAI 8578 (pp. 146–160). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.
Cheng, P. C.-H. (2004). Why diagrams are (sometimes) six times easier than words: Benefits beyond locational indexing. In A. F. Blackwell, K. Marriott, & A. Shimojima (Eds.), Proceedings of Diagrams 2004, LNAI 2980 (pp. 242–260). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.
Deloache, J. S., Sugarman, S., & Brown, A. L. (1985). The development of error correction strategies in young children’s manipulative play. Child Development, 56, 928–939.
Dickstein, L. S. (1978). The effect of figure on syllogistic reasoning. Memory and Cognition, 6, 76–83.
Dickstein, L. S. (1981). The meaning of conversion in syllogistic reasoning. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 18, 135–138.
Dobson, M. (1999). Information enforcement and learning with interactive graphical systems. Learning and Instruction, 9, 365–390.
Doumas, L. A., Hummel, J. E., & Sandhofer, C. M. (2008). A theory of the discovery and predication of relational concepts. Psychological Review, 115, 1–43.
Edwards, A. W. F. (2004). Cogwheels of the mind: The story of venn diagrams. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Englebretsen, G. (1992). Linear diagrams for syllogisms (with relationals). Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 33, 37–69.
Erickson, J. R. (1974). A set analysis theory of behavior in formal syllogistic reasoning tasks. In R. Solso (Ed.), Loyola symposium on cognition (Vol. 2, pp. 305–329). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Euler, L. (1768). Lettres à une Princesse d’Allemagne sur Divers Sujets de Physique et de Philosophie. Saint-Pétersbourg: De l’Académie des Sciences.
Evans, J St B T. (2003). In two minds: Dual-process accounts of reasoning. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 454–459.
Evans, J. S. B. T. (2008). Dual processing accounts of reasoning, judgment, and social cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 255–278.
Evans, J. S. B. T., Newstead, S. E., & Byrne, R. J. (1993). Human reasoning: The psychology of deduction. Hove: Erlbaum.
Fish, A., Khazaei, B., & Roast, C. (2011). User-comprehension of Euler diagrams. Journal of Visual Languages and Computing, 22, 340–354.
Ford, M. (1994). Two modes of mental representation and problem solution in syllogistic reasoning. Cognition, 54, 1–71.
Gattis, M. (2005). Inferencing from spatial information. Spatial Cognition and Computation, 5, 119–137.
Gergonne, J. D. (1817). Essai de dialectique rationelle. Annuales de Mathematiques Pures et Appliqukes, 7, 189–228.
Geis, M. L., & Zwicky, A. M. (1971). On invited inferences. Linguistic Inquiry, 2, 561–566.
Geurts, B. (2003). Reasoning with quantifiers. Cognition, 86, 223–251.
Geurts, B. (2007). Existential import. In I. Comorovski & K. von Heusinger (Eds.), Existence: Semantics and syntax (pp. 253–271). Netherlands: Springer.
Glasgow, J., Narayanan, N. H., & Chandrasekaran, B. (Eds.). (1995). Diagrammatic reasoning: Cognitive & computational perspectives. Cambridge, MA: AAAI Press/MIT Press.
Greenfield, P. M., Nelson, K., & Saltzman, E. (1972). The development of rulebound strategies for manipulating seriated cups: A parallel between action and grammar. Cognitive Psychology, 3, 291–310.
Gurr, C. A., Lee, J., & Stenning, K. (1998). Theories of diagrammatic reasoning: Distinguishing component problems. Minds and Machines, 8, 533–557.
Halford, G. S., Wilson, W. H., & Phillips, S. (1998). Processing capacity defined by relational complexity: Implications for comparative, developmental, and cognitive psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21, 803–831.
Halford, G. S., Wilson, W. H., & Phillips, S. (2010). Relational knowledge: The foundation of higher cognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14, 497–505.
Hammer, E., & Shin, S. (1998). Euler’s visual logic. History and Philosophy of Logic, 19, 1–29.
Hegarty, M. (2004). Mechanical reasoning by mental simulation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 280–285.
Heiser, J., & Tversky, B. (2006). Arrows in comprehending and producing mechanical diagrams. Cognitive Science, 30, 581–592.
Hertzum, M., & Frøkjær, E. (1996). Browsing and querying in online documentation: A study of user interfaces and the interaction process. ACM Transactions on Computer–Human Interaction, 3, 136–161.
Hodes, H. T. (1984). Logicism and the ontological commitments of arithmetic. Journal of Philosophy, 81, 123–49.
Horn, L. R. (2000). From if to iff: Conditional perfection as pragmatic strengthening. Journal of Pragmatics, 32, 289–326.
Howse, J., Molina, F., Shin, S.-J., & Taylor, J. (2002). On diagram tokens and types. In M. Hegarty, B. Meyer, & N. H. Narayanan (Eds.), Proceedings of Diagrams 2002, LNAI 2317 (pp. 146–160). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.
Howse, J., Stapleton, G., & Taylor, J. (2005). Spider diagrams. LMS Journal of Computation and Mathematics, 8, 145–194.
Johnson, M. (1987). The body in the mind: The bodily basis of meaning, imagination, and reason. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.
Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1983). Mental models: Towards cognitive science of language, inference, and consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Johnson-Laird, P. N., & Byrne, R. (1991). Deduction. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Johnson-Pynn, J., Fragaszy, D. M., Hirsh, E. M., Brakke, K. E., & Greenfield, P. M. (1999). Strategies used to combine seriated cups by chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes), bonobos (Pan paniscus), and capuchins (Cebus apella). Journal of Comparative Psychology, 113, 137–148.
Jones, S., McInnes, S., & Staveley, M. S. (1999). A graphical user interface for Boolean query specification. International Journal of Digital Library, 2, 207–223.
Kneale, W., & Kneale, M. (1962). The development of logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Khemlani, S., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. (2012). Theories of the syllogism: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 138, 427–457.
Lambert, J. H. (1764). Neues Organon oder Gedanken über die Erforschung und Bezeichnung des Wahren und dessen Unterscheidung vom Irrtum und Schein. Leipzig: Johann Wendler.
Lakoff, G., & Nún̈ez, R. E. (2000). Where mathematics comes from: How the embodied mind brings mathematics into being. New York, NY: Basic Books.
Larkin, J., & Simon, H. (1987). Why a diagram is (sometimes) worth 10,000 words. Cognitive Science, 11, 65–99.
Leibniz, G.W. (1903/1988). Opuscules et fragments inèdits: extraits des manuscrits de la bibliothèque royale de Hanovre. L. Couturat (ed). Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlag.
Lemon, O., & Pratt, I. (1998). On the insufficiency of linear diagrams for syllogisms. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 39, 573–580.
Leslie, S. J., & Gelman, S. A. (2012). Quantified statements are recalled as generics: Evidence from preschool children and adults. Cognitive Psychology, 64, 186–214.
Lull, R. (1617). Opera Ea Quae Ad Adinventam Ab Ipso Artem Universalem, Scientiarum Artiumque Omnium Breui Compendio, Firmaq́; Memoria Apprehendendarum, Locupletiffimaq́; Vel Oratione Ex Tempore Pertractandarum, Pertinent. Strassburg: Lazari Zetzneri.
MacFarlane, J. (2002). Frege, Kant, and the logic in logicism. The Philosophical Review, 111, 25–65.
Meilinger, T., & Knauff, M. (2008). Ask for directions or use a map: A field experiment on spatial orientation and wayfinding in an urban environment. Journal of Spatial Science, 53, 13–23.
Michard, A. (1982). Graphical presentation of boolean expressions in a database query language: Design notes and an ergonomic evaluation. Behaviour and Information Technology, 1, 279–288.
Mineshima, K., Okada, M., Sato, Y., & Takemura, R. (2008). Diagrammatic reasoning system with Euler circles: Theory and experiment design. In G. Stapleton, J. Howse, & J. Lee (Eds.), Proceedings of Diagrams 2008, LNAI 5223 (pp. 188–205). Berlin Heidelberg: Springer.
Mineshima, K., Okada, M., & Takemura, R. (2012a). A diagrammatic reasoning system with Euler circles. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 21, 365–391.
Mineshima, K., Okada, M., & Takemura, R. (2012b). A generalized syllogistic inference system based on inclusion and exclusion relations. Studia Logica, 100, 753–785.
Mineshima, K., Sato, Y., Takemura, R., & Okada, M. (2014). Towards explaining the cognitive efficacy of Euler diagrams in syllogistic reasoning: A relational perspective. Journal of Visual Languages and Computing, 25, 156–169.
Monaghan, P., & Stenning, K. (1998). Effects of representational modality and thinking style on learning to solve reasoning problems. In M. A. Gernsbacher & S. J. Derry (Eds.), Proceedings of the 20th annual conference of the cognitive science society (pp. 716–721). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Myers, K. L., & Konolige, K. (1994). Reasoning with analogical representations. In G. Lakemeyer & B. Nebel (Eds.), Foundations of knowledge representation and reasoning, LNAI 810 (pp. 229–249). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.
Newstead, S. E., & Griggs, R. (1983). Drawing inferences from quantified statements: A study of the square of opposition. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 22, 535–546.
Palmer, S. (1978). Fundamental aspects of cognitive representation. In E. Rosch & B. Lloyd (Eds.), Cognition and categorization (pp. 259–303). New Jersey: Lawrence Elbaum.
Peirce, C.S. (1897/1933). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce IV. In C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss (Eds.), Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Pfeifer, N., & Kleiter, G. D. (2005). Towards a mental probability logic. Psychologica Belgica, 45, 71–100.
Politzer, G., van der Henst, J.-B., Luche, C. D., & Noveck, I. A. (2006). The interpretation of classically quantified sentences: A set-theoretic approach. Cognitive Science, 30, 691–723.
Politzer, G., & Mercier, H. (2008). Solving categorical syllogisms with singular premises. Thinking and Reasoning, 14, 414–453.
Pratt, I. (1993). Map semantics. In A. U. Frank & I. Campari (Eds.), Spatial information theory: A theoretical basis for GIS, LNCS 716 (pp. 77–91). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.
Purchase, H. C. (2014). Twelve years of diagrams research. Journal of Visual Languages and Computing, 25, 57–75.
Rescorla, M. (2009). Predication and cartographic representation. Synthese, 169, 175–200.
Revlis, R. (1975). Two models of syllogistic reasoning: Feature selection and conversion. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 14, 180–195.
Rizzo, A., & Palmonari, M. (2005). The mediating role of artifacts in deductive reasoning. In B. G. Bara, L. Barsalou & M. Bucciarelli (Eds.), Proceedings of the 27th annual conference of the cognitive science society (pp. 1862–1867). Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society.
Roberts, M. J., Newstead, S. E., & Griggs, R. A. (2001). Quanntifier interpretation and syllogistic reasoning. Thinking and Reasoning, 7, 173–204.
Rodgers, P. (2014). A survey of Euler diagrams. Journal of Visual Languages and Computing, 25, 134–155.
Sato, Y., Mineshima, K., & Takemura, R. (2010). Constructing internal diagrammatic proofs from external logic diagrams. In R. Catrambone & S. Ohlsson (Eds.), Proceedings of the 32nd annual conference of the cognitive science society (pp. 2668–2673). Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society.
Sato, Y., Mineshima, K., & Takemura, R. (2011). Interpreting logic diagrams: A comparison of two formulations of diagrammatic representations. In C. Hoelscher, T. F. Shipley & L. Carlson (Eds.), Proceedings of the 33rd annual conference of the cognitive science society (pp. 2182–2187). Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society.
Sato, Y., Masuda, S., Someya, Y., Tsujii, T., & Watanabe, S. (2015). An fMRI analysis of the efficacy of Euler diagrams in logical reasoning. In Proceedings of 2015 IEEE symposium on visual languages and human-centric computing (9 pp). Los Alamitos, CA: IEEE Computer Society Press.
Scaife, M., & Rogers, Y. (1996). External cognition: How do graphical representations work? International Journal of Human–Computer Studies, 45, 185–213.
Shimojima, A. (1996). On the efficacy of representation. PhD thesis, Indiana University.
Shimojima, A., & Katagiri, Y. (2013). An eye-tracking study of exploitations of spatial constraints in diagrammatic reasoning. Cognitive Science, 37, 211–254.
Shin, S.-J. (1994). The logical status of diagrams. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Stapleton, G. (2005). A survey of reasoning systems based on Euler diagrams. Proceedings of Euler diagrams 2004, ENTCS 134 (pp. 127–151). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Stenning, K. (2002). Seeing reason: Image and language in learning to think. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stenning, K., Cox, R., & Oberlander, J. (1995). Contrasting the cognitive effects of graphical and sentential logic teaching: Reasoning, representation and individual differences. Language and Cognitive Processes, 10, 333–354.
Stenning, K., & Oberlander, J. (1995). A cognitive theory of graphical and linguistic reasoning. Cognitive Science, 19, 97–140.
Stenning, K., & Lemon, O. (2001). Aligning logical and psychological perspectives on diagrammatic reasoning. Artificial Intelligence Review, 15, 29–62.
Stenning, K., & van Lambalgen, M. (2001). Semantics as a foundation for psychology: A case study of Wason’s selection task. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 10, 273–317.
Stenning, K., & van Lambalgen, M. (2004). A little logic goes a long way: Basing experiment on semantic theory in the cognitive science of conditional reasoning. Cognitive Science, 28, 481–529.
Stenning, K., & van Lambalgen, M. (2008). Human reasoning and cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Sugimoto, Y., & Sato, Y. (2015). A specification-aware modeling of syllogistic reasoning with mental models. In N. A. Taatgen, M. K. van Vugt, J. P. Borst & K. Mehlhorn (Eds.), Proceedings of the 13th international conference on cognitive modeling (pp. 31–36). Groningen, The Netherlands: University of Groningen.
Szymanik, J., & Zajenkowski, M. (2010). Comprehension of simple quantifiers: Empirical evaluation of a computational model. Cognitive Science, 34, 521–532.
Takemura, R. (2013). Proof theory for reasoning with Euler diagrams: A logic translation and normalization. Studia Logica, 101, 157–191.
Venn, J. (1881). Symbolic logic. London: Macmillan.
Westerståhl, D. (1989). Quantifiers in formal and natural languages. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. 4, pp. 2–132). Dordrecht: Reidel.
Zhang, J., & Norman, D. A. (1994). Representations in distributed cognitive tasks. Cognitive Science, 18, 87–122.
Acknowledgments
Parts of this study were presented at the 6th Diagrams Conference (August, 2010) in Portland and the 7th Diagrams Conference (July, 2012) in Canterbury. This study was partially supported by Grant-in-Aid for JSPS Fellows (21\(\cdot \)7357; 25\(\cdot \)2291) to the first author. The authors would like to thank Mitsuhiro Okada, Atsushi Shimojima, Ryo Takemura, and Keith Stenning for the valuable advice and Philip Johnson-Laird and Malcolm Bauer for permission to use unpublished results.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Appendices
Appendix 1: The Results of Each Syllogistic Type
The results of each syllogistic type are shown in Tables 5 and 6. Numbers indicate the percentage of total responses to each syllogism. Bold type refers to valid conclusion by the standard of predicate logic. For simplicity, we exclude the conclusions of the so-called “weak” syllogisms (syllogisms whose validity depends on the existential import of subject term) from valid answers.
Appendix 2: Solving Processes Using Euler Diagrams
1.1 Single Type
1.2 Multiple Type (Valid)
1.3 Multiple Type (Invalid)
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Sato, Y., Mineshima, K. How Diagrams Can Support Syllogistic Reasoning: An Experimental Study. J of Log Lang and Inf 24, 409–455 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-015-9225-4
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-015-9225-4