Abstract
I consider a game in which imperfectly informed jurors vote to select one of several possible choices when there is a natural ordering of the possibilities. Each juror votes for the largest alternative the juror would like to implement, and the alternative that is selected is the largest alternative supported by a given number of jurors. For non-unanimous voting rules, the probability of a mistaken judgment goes to zero as the number of jurors goes to infinity. I also give necessary and sufficient conditions to obtain asymptotic efficiency under unanimous voting rules, and show that unanimous rules may lead to a bias in which moderate outcomes are never chosen.
Similar content being viewed by others
References
Austen-Smith D, Banks JS (1996) Information aggregation, rationality, and the Condorcet jury theorem. Am Polit Sci Rev 90: 34–45
Berend D, Paroush D (1998) When is Condorcet’s jury theorem valid?. Soc Choice Welf 15: 481–488
Berg S (1993) Condorcet’s jury theorem dependency among jurors. Soc Choice Welf 10: 87–95
Condorcet M (1785) Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix. De l’Imprimerie Royale, Paris
Duggan J, Martinelli C (2001) A Bayesian model of voting in juries. Games Econ Behav 37: 259–294
Feddersen T, Pesendorfer W (1998) Convicting the innocent: the inferiority of unanimous jury verdicts under strategic voting. Am Polit Sci Rev 92: 23–35
Fey M (2003) A note on the Condorcet jury theorem with supermajority voting rules. Soc Choice Welf 20: 27–32
Gerardi D (2000) Jury verdicts and preference diversity. Am Polit Sci Rev 94: 395–406
Ladha KK (1992) The Condorcet jury theorem, free speech, and correlated votes. Am J Polit Sci 36: 617–634
Ladha KK (1995) Information pooling through majority-rule voting: Condorcet’s jury theorem with correlated votes. J Econ Behav Organ 26: 353–372
Martinelli C (2002) Convergence results for unanimous voting. J Econ Theory 105: 278–297
McLennan A (1998) Consequences of the Condorcet jury theorem for beneficial information aggregation by rational agents. Am Polit Sci Rev 92: 413–418
Meirowitz A (2002) Informative voting and Condorcet jury theorems with a continuum of types. Soc Choice Welf 19: 219–236
Milgrom PR (1979) A convergence theorem for competitive bidding with differential information. Econometrica 47: 679–688
Milgrom PR (1981) Rational expectations, information acquisition, and competitive bidding. Econometrica 49: 921–943
Myerson RB (1998) Extended Poisson games and the Condorcet jury theorem. Games Econ Behav 25: 111–131
Pesendorfer W, Swinkels JM (1997) The loser’s curse and information aggregation in common value auctions. Econometrica 65: 1247–1281
Selvin M, Picus L (1987) The debate over jury performance: observations from a recent asbestos case. Rand Institute for Civil Justice, Santa Monica
Wilson RB (1977) A bidding model of perfect competition. Rev Econ Stud 44: 511–518
Wit J (1998) Rational choice and the Condorcet jury theorem. Games Econ Behav 22: 364–376
Young HP (1988) Condorcet’s theory of voting. Am Polit Sci Rev 82: 1231–1244
Young P (1995) Optimal voting rules. J Econ Perspect 9: 51–64
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
I thank Kenneth Shotts and an anonymous associate editor for comments and NSF for financial support.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Hummel, P. Jury theorems with multiple alternatives. Soc Choice Welf 34, 65–103 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-009-0389-1
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-009-0389-1