Abstract
We prove that every weakly square compact cardinal is a strong limit cardinal, and therefore weakly compact. We also study Aronszajn trees with no uncountable finitely splitting subtrees, characterizing them in terms of being Lindelöf with respect to a particular topology. We prove that the class of such trees is consistently non-empty and lies between the classes of Suslin and Aronszajn trees.
Similar content being viewed by others
Avoid common mistakes on your manuscript.
1 Introduction
Recall that a topological space is Lindelöf if and only if every open cover has a countable subcover. Unlike compactness, the Lindelöf property need not be presserved by finite products, as shown by the classical Sorgenfrey line example, which is the space X with underlying set \(\mathbb {R}\) and topology generated by all left-closed right-open intervals. This space is Lindelöf, but the uncountable set \(\{(x,-x):x\in \mathbb {R}\}\) is closed and discrete in \(X^2\), hence \(X^2\) is not Lindelöf. For details, see [10, Counterexample 84].
Extending this to larger cardinals \(\kappa \), we say that a topological space X is \(\kappa \)-compact if and only if every open cover of X has a subcover of size less than \(\kappa \). So, compact is \(\aleph _0\)-compact and Lindelöf is \(\aleph _1\)-compact. In connection with this, Hajnal and Juhàsz [3] introduced the following large cardinal notion: an infinite cardinal \(\kappa \) is square compact if and only if for every \(\kappa \)-compact space X, \(X^2\) is \(\kappa \)-compact. This is in fact equivalent to the product of any two \(\kappa \)-compact spaces being \(\kappa \)-compact. For the non-trivial direction, if X and Y are \(\kappa \)-compact, then so is their disjoint sum \(X\oplus Y\). By assumption, \((X\oplus Y)^2\) is \(\kappa \)-compact. Since \(X\times Y\) is a closed subset of \((X\oplus Y)^2\), it follows that \(X\times Y\) is \(\kappa \)-compact too.
Recall that the weight w(X) of a topological space X is the least size of a base for the topology on X. A refined version of square compactness, graduated by weights, was introduced by Buhagiar and Dz̆amonja in their 2021 paper [1]: given some cardinal \(\lambda \), an infinite cardinal \(\kappa \) is \(\lambda \)-square compact if and only if for every space X of weight \(\le \lambda \), if X is \(\kappa \)-compact, then \(X^2\) is \(\kappa \)-compact They (and we) say that \(\kappa \) is weakly square compact if and only if it is \(\kappa \)-square compact.
In this terminology, the results in [3] can be stated as:
Theorem
(Hajnal-Juhàsz [3, Theorem 1]) Every weakly square compact cardinal is regular.
Theorem
(Hajnal-Juhàsz [3, Theorem 2]) Suppose that \(\kappa \) is uncountable. If \(\kappa \) is \(2^\kappa \)-square compact, then it is weakly compact.
This shows that the existence of \(\kappa \) which is \(2^\kappa \)-square compact is already a large cardinal notion. In [1], Buhagiar and Dz̆amonja undertake a closer study of weak square compactness, and give a variety of equivalent formulations. In particular, they proved the following:
Theorem
(Buhagiar-Dz̆amonja, [1, Theorem 5.1]) Let \(\kappa \) be an uncountable cardinal. Suppose that \(\kappa ^{<\kappa }=\kappa \). Then \(\kappa \) is weakly compact if and only if it is weakly square compact.
Note that if \(\kappa \) is weakly compact, then \(\kappa ^{<\kappa }=\kappa \). The same is not obviously true if instead \(\kappa \) is \(\kappa \)-square compact. The first result we establish in this paper is that indeed \(\kappa =\kappa ^{<\kappa }\) whenever \(\kappa \) is \(\kappa \)-square compact, thereby removing the cardinal arithmetic assumption from the Buhagiar-Dz̆amonja theorem. This is done by generalizing the Sorgenfrey line construction.
As far as we know, strong compactness continues to be the best upper bound for the consistency strength of full square compactness, see [5, Theorem 5.11], [8] and [1, Theorem 2.10]. Sharper upper bounds for the consistency strength of “There exists \(\kappa \) which is \(2^\kappa \)-square compact" appear in [1, Theorem 6.1].
Having studied topologies on linear orders, we turn to looking at topologies on trees, with a view towards introducing new examples of Lindelöf spaces. In the survey [9], Nyikos considers a total of ten different topologies on trees. Of these, only two are always Hausdorff, and we adhere to the doctrine of only considering Hausdorff spaces. By [9, Theorem 3.6], the coarse wedge topology appears uninteresting for our purposes, since it is \(\omega _1\)-compactFootnote 1 if and only if the underlying tree has countably many minimal elements. This leaves us with only the fine wedge topology to focus on. We give a tree-theoretic characterization of being Lindelöf with respect to this topology. First, some terminology: we say that a tree is finitely splitting if and only if every point in the tree has finitely many immediate successors. A tree is infinitely splitting if and only if every point in the tree has infinitely many immediate successors. A subtree of a tree T is a set \(S\subseteq T\) such that for all \(x\in S\) and \(y\in T\), if \(y<x\), then \(y\in S\).
Theorem
Let T be an infinitely splitting \(\aleph _1\)-tree. Then T is Lindelöf with respect to the fine-wedge topology if and only if every finitely splitting subtree of T is countable.
We shall show that, for infinitely splitting trees,
Here, by Lindelöf we mean Lindelöf with respect to the fine-wedge topology.
Given a partially ordered set X, we let \(X^*\) denote the dual order on X, that is \(x<^* y\) if and only if \(y<x\).
A tree is a pair \((T,<_T)\) such that \(<_T\) is a strict partial order on T and \(\{y\in T:y<_Tx\}\) is well-ordered for every \(x\in T\). We will usually suppress the subscript in \(<_T\) and identify the tree with its underlying set when there is no danger of confusion.
Elements of a tree are referred to as nodes or points. We say \(x,y\in T\) are comparable, denoted \(x\parallel y\), if and only if \(x\le _T y\) or \(y\le _T x\). Otherwise, we say that x and y are incomparable, denoted \(x\perp y\). The height of a node \(x\in T\) is the order-type of the set \(\{y\in T:y<_T x\}\), denoted \(\textrm{ht}_T(x)\) (or simply \(\textrm{ht}(x)\)). Given an ordinal \(\alpha \), level \(\alpha \) of the tree is the set \(T_\alpha =\{x\in T:\textrm{ht}_T(x)=\alpha \}\). The height \(h_T(T)\) of T is defined by \(\textrm{ht}(T)=\min \{\alpha :T_\alpha =\emptyset \}\). Given an ordinal \(\alpha <\textrm{ht}(T)\), we let \(T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha =\{x\in T:\textrm{ht}(x)<\alpha \}\), which is of course a subtree of T of height \(\alpha \). Given \(x\in T\), we let \(I_T(x)\) denote the set of immediate successors of x, and write I(x) when there is no possibility of confusion.
2 Square compactness
We shall say a space X is hereditarily \(\kappa \)-compact if and only if every subspace of X is \(\kappa \)-compact. For example, any space of weight less than \(\kappa \) is hereditarily \(\kappa \)-compact.
A useful criterion for hereditary \(\kappa \)-compactness is
Lemma 2.1
Let \((X,\tau )\) be a topological space. Then X is hereditarily \(\kappa \)-compact if and only if for every \(\mathcal U\subseteq \tau \) there is some \(\mathcal {U}_0\in [\mathcal {U}]^{<\kappa }\) with \(\bigcup \mathcal {U}=\bigcup \mathcal {U}_0\).
Proof
\(\Rightarrow \)) Given \(\mathcal {U}\), consider the subspace \(\bigcup \mathcal {U}\).
\(\Leftarrow \)) Suppose \(Y\subseteq X\) is not \(\kappa \)-compact. Fix some \(\mathcal U\subseteq \tau \) such that \(\bigcup \mathcal {U}\supseteq Y\) but there is no \(\mathcal {U}_0\in [\mathcal {U}]^{<\kappa }\) with \(\bigcup \mathcal {U}_0\supseteq Y\). Then \(\bigcup \mathcal {U}_0\ne \bigcup \mathcal {U}\) for every \(\mathcal {U}_0\in [\mathcal {U}]^{<\kappa }\).\(\square \)
The following is obvious:
Lemma 2.2
Suppose that \((X,\tau )\) is \(\kappa \)-compact and \(Y\subseteq X\) is closed. Then Y is \(\kappa \)-compact with the subspace topology.
As mentioned in the introduction, Hajnal and Juhàsz already proved that weak square compactness entails regularity. To deal with the (strong) inaccessibility of \(\kappa \), we will generalize the classical construction of the Sorgenfrey line to larger linear orders.
Definition 2.3
Let \((X,<)\) be a dlo (dense linear order without end-points). The density of X, denoted d(X), is the cardinal
This of course coincides with the density of X as a topological spacer under the order topology.
For example, \(d(\mathbb {R})=\aleph _0\). It is straightforward to show that w(X), the weight of X with respect to the order topology, is exactly d(X).
Definition 2.4
Given a dlo \((X,<)\), the family \(\{[x,y):x,y\in X\wedge x<y\}\) forms a base for a topology on X, which we shall call the Sorgenfrey topology.
Lemma 2.5
Let \((X,<)\) be a dlo with \(d(X)<\kappa \). Then the Sorgenfrey topology on X is hereditarily \(\kappa \)-compact.
Proof
Let \(\mathcal {U}\subseteq \{[x,y):x,y\in X\}\) and let \(W=\bigcup \{(x,y):[x,y)\in \mathcal {U}\}\). Obviously, W is open with respect to the order topology on X, which has weight less than \(\kappa \). By Lemma 2.1, \(W=\bigcup \{(x,y):[x,y)\in \mathcal {U}_0\}\) for some \(\mathcal {U}_0\in [\mathcal {U}]^{<\kappa }\). Let \(A:=(\bigcup \mathcal {U})\setminus W\).\(\square \)
Claim
\(|A|<\kappa \).
Proof of Claim
Fix \(D\in [X]^{<\kappa }\) dense in the order topology. For each \(x\in A\), find \([a_x,b_x)\in \mathcal {U}\) such that \(x\in [a_x,b_x)\). Since \(x\not \in W\), we infer that \(x=a_x<b_x\), so we can pick some \(d_x\in D\) with \(x<d_x<b_x\). Now suppose \(x,y\in A\) with \(x<y\). Since \(y\not \in W\), \(b_x\le y\). Then \(d_x<b_x\le y<d_y\), so \(d_x<d_y\). Therefore, \(x\mapsto d_x\) is an injective map from A into D.
For each \(x\in A\), pick \(U_x\in \mathcal {U}\) with \(x\in U_x\). Let \(\mathcal {U}_1=\{U_x:x\in A\}\). Clearly, \(|\mathcal {U}_1|<\kappa \). We now have that \(\mathcal {U}_2=\mathcal {U}_0\cup \mathcal {U}_1\in [\mathcal {U}]^{<\kappa }\) and \(\bigcup \mathcal {U}_2=\bigcup \mathcal {U}\).
Lemma 2.6
Let \(\kappa >\omega \) be a cardinal. Suppose that there is a dlo \((X,<)\) with \(d(X)<\kappa =|X|\). Then \(\kappa \) is not \(\kappa \)-square compact.
Proof
Replacing X by \(X\oplus X^*\) if necessary, we may assume that \((X,<)\) admits an order reversing involution, which we shall suggestively denote by \(x\mapsto -x\).
Let \(\tau \) be the Sorgenfrey topology on X. Note that \(w(X,\tau )\le \kappa \), because \(|X|\le \kappa \), and that \((X,\tau )\) is \(\kappa \)-compact by lemma 2.5. It therefore suffices to show that \(X^2\) is not \(\kappa \)-compact with respect to the product topology. Let
Since \(x\mapsto -x\) is order-reversing, it is continuous with respect to the order topology \(\tau _<\), hence Y is closed in \((X^2,\tau _<\otimes \tau _<)\). But \(\tau _<\subseteq \tau \), so Y is closed in \((X^2,\tau \otimes \tau )\). For each \(x\in X\), pick \(u_x,v_x\in X\) with \(u_x<x<v_x\). Now observe that
We have shown that Y is discrete in \((X^2,\tau \otimes \tau )\). Since \(|Y|=\kappa \), Y is not \(\kappa \)-compact, and so neither is \((X^2,\tau \otimes \tau )\) because Y is closed.\(\square \)
The goal now is to build large dlo’s with small density. This will be possible, under certain cardinal arithmetic constraints. Our original construction was rather convoluted, and we thank Will Brian for suggesting the following simpler approach.
Lemma 2.7
Let \(\kappa \ge \omega _1\). Suppose there exist infinite cardinals \(\mu \) and \(\theta \) such that \(\mu ^{<\theta }=\mu <\kappa \le \mu ^\theta \). Then there is a dlo X with \(d(X)<\kappa =|X|\).
Proof
Let \(Y:={}^\theta \mu \), ordered lexicographically. Note that \(|Y|=\mu ^\theta \ge \kappa \). Let D be the set of sequences in Y which are eventually 0. Then D is dense in Y and \(|D|=\mu ^{<\theta }<\kappa \). By the Downward Lowenheim-Skölem theorem, find \(X\prec Y\) with \(D\subseteq X\) and \(|X|=\kappa \). Since D is dense in X, \(d(X)<\kappa \).\(\square \)
Theorem 2.8
Let \(\kappa \ge \omega _1\). If there are cardinals \(\mu \) and \(\theta \) such that \(\mu ^{<\theta }=\mu <\kappa \le \mu ^\theta \), then \(\kappa \) is not \(\kappa \)-square compact.
Proof
Immediate from Lemmas 2.6 and 2.7.\(\square \)
Corollary 2.9
Suppose \(\lambda \ge \omega \). Then \(\lambda ^+\) is not \(\lambda ^+\)-square compact.
Proof
Let \(\theta :=\min \{\nu :\lambda ^\nu >\lambda \}\). By König’s lemma, \(\theta \le \textrm{cf}(\lambda )\), so \(\lambda ^{<\theta }=\lambda \) by the minimality of \(\theta \). Now apply Lemma 2.7 with \(\kappa =\lambda ^+\) and \(\mu =\lambda \).\(\square \)
In particular, if \(\kappa \) is \(\kappa \)-square compact, then \(\kappa \) is a limit cardinal, hence weakly inaccessible. In fact, this can be improved:
Corollary 2.10
Suppose \(\kappa \) is \(\kappa \)-square compact. Then \(\kappa \) is strongly inaccessible.
Proof
The fact that \(\kappa \) is regular under the hypothesis was already mentioned in the introduction, and follows from [3, Theorem 1].
Suppose \(\kappa \) is not strong limit. Let
To see that this is well defined, fix \(\delta <\kappa \) so that \(2^\delta \ge \kappa \), and take \(\lambda =\nu =\delta \).
Having fixed \(\theta \), let \(\lambda <\kappa \) be the least witness to the definition of \(\theta \), that is \(\theta \le \lambda < \kappa \le \lambda ^\theta \) and \(\lambda \) is least with these properties. Note that, if \(\alpha <\theta \), then \(\lambda ^\alpha <\kappa \), since otherwise \(\alpha \) contradicts the minimal choice of \(\theta \).\(\square \)
Claim 1
\(\theta \) is regular.
Proof of Claim 1
Suppose not, say \(\theta ^*=\textrm{cf}(\theta )<\theta \). Fix \({\langle {\theta _\xi :\xi <\theta ^*}\rangle }\) cofinal in \(\theta \). By the minimality of \(\theta \), \(\lambda ^{\theta _\xi }<\kappa \) for every \(\xi <\theta ^*\). Let \(\lambda ^*:=\sup \{\lambda ^{\theta _\xi }:\xi <\theta ^*\}\). Since \(\kappa \) is regular and \(\theta ^*<\theta <\kappa \), it follows that \(\lambda ^*<\kappa \). We therefore have
This contradicts the minimality of \(\theta \).
Put \(\mu =\lambda ^{<\theta }\). Again, \(\mu <\kappa \), because \(\lambda ^\alpha <\kappa \) for \(\alpha <\theta \) and \(\theta <\kappa =\textrm{cf}(\kappa )\). Also, \(\mu ^\theta \ge \lambda ^\theta \ge \kappa \).
Claim 2
\(\mu ^{<\theta }=\mu \).
Proof of Claim 2
We consider two separate cases.
Case 1: \(\alpha \mapsto \lambda ^\alpha \) is eventually constant for \(\alpha <\theta \). Note that this includes the case when \(\theta \) is a successor cardinal. By definition of \(\mu \), the eventual constant value must be \(\mu \), so \(\lambda ^\alpha =\mu \) for all large enough \(\alpha <\theta \). But then \(\mu ^\alpha =\mu \) whenever \(\alpha <\theta \) is sufficiently big, hence \(\mu ^{<\theta }=\mu \).
Case 2: \(\lambda ^\alpha \) is not eventually constant for \(\alpha <\theta \). As \(\theta \) is regular, \(\textrm{cf}(\mu )=\theta \). So, if \(\alpha <\theta \), we have
Therefore, \(\mu ^{<\theta }=\mu \).
Therefore, \(\mu ,\theta \) and \(\kappa \) satisfy the conditions of Theorem 2.7, so \(\kappa \) is not \(\kappa \)-square compact.
Theorem 2.11
Let \(\kappa \) be an uncountable cardinal. Then \(\kappa \) is weakly compact if and only if it is \(\kappa \)-square compact.
Proof
The forwards direction can be found in [3, Theorem 2]. The backwards direction is in [1, Theorem 5.1], under the additional hypothesis that \(\kappa ^{<\kappa }=\kappa \). But this is redundant when \(\kappa \) is \(\kappa \)-square compact, because \(\kappa \) is strongly inaccessible by Corollary 2.10.\(\square \)
3 The fine wedge topology
Let \((T,<)\) be a tree. If \(X\subseteq T\), we let \(\mathord {\uparrow }X:=\{y\in T:\exists x\in X(x\le y)\}\). If \(X=\{x\}\), we write \(\mathord {\uparrow }x\) instead of \(\mathord {\uparrow }\{x\}\). The symbols \(\mathord {\downarrow }X\) and \(\mathord {\downarrow }x\) are defined analogously.
If T is a tree, the fine wedge topology on T is generated by the sets \(\mathord {\uparrow }t\) and their complements, where \(t\in T\).
Note that, if \(x<y\), then \((\mathord {\uparrow }x) \setminus \mathord {\uparrow }y\) and \(\mathord {\uparrow }y\) are disjoint open neighbourhoods of x and y, respectively. If \(x\perp y\), then \(\mathord {\uparrow }x\) and \(\mathord {\uparrow }y\) are disjoint open neighbourhoods of x and y. We have thus shown that the topology is Hausdorff.
All topological notions below refer to the fine wedge topology.
Remark 3.1
If T is finitely splitting at x (that is \(|I(x)|<\aleph _0\)), then the identity
shows that x is isolated. Therefore, if T is finitely splitting, the fine wedge topology is just the discrete topology on T. The interplay between finite and infinitely splitting trees will play a key role in our work, see Theorem 3.8.
Recall that, if X is a topological space and \(x\in X\), we say that a collection of open sets \(\mathcal B\) is a neighbourhood base at x if and only if for every open set U with \(x\in U\) there is some \(B\in \mathcal B\) with \(x\in B\subseteq U\). We define the character of x to be the cardinal \(\chi (x,X):=\min \{|\mathcal B|:\mathcal {B} \text { is a neighbourhood base at }x\}\).
Lemma 3.2
Let T be a tree. Given \(x\in T\), the sets
where \(F\in [I(x)]^{<\omega }\), form a neighbourhood base at x, and so \(\chi (x,T)=|I(x)|\). In particular, if every node has \(\aleph _0\) many immediate successors, then the fine-wedge topology is first countable.
Proof
Let U be a basic open neighbourhood of x, say
for some \(x_i,y_j\in T\), \(n,m\in \omega \). Let \(J=\{j<m:x< y_j\}\). For each \(j\in J\), let \(z_j\in I(x)\) be the unique point with \(z_j\le y_j\). Then
which completes the proof.\(\square \)
We isolate the following elementary result from general topology, whose proof is easy and hence omitted:
Lemma 3.3
Let X be a topological space and \(\kappa \) an infinite cardinal. Suppose we have a sequence \({\langle {\mathcal {B}_x:x\in X}\rangle }\) such that \(\mathcal {B}_x\) is a neighbourhood base at x for every \(x\in X\). Then X is \(\kappa \)-compact if and only if for each \(\Gamma \in \prod _{x\in X}\mathcal {B}_x\) there is some \(Y\in [X]^{<\kappa }\) such that \(X=\bigcup _{y\in Y} \Gamma (y)\).
In the tree context, we’ll be looking at the system of neighbourhood bases formed by the sets \(\mathord {\uparrow }x\setminus \mathord {\uparrow }f(x)\), where \(f\in \prod _{x\in T}[I(x)]^{<\omega }\). We shall say that such an f codes the cover \(\mathcal {U}_f:=\{\mathord {\uparrow }x{\setminus } \mathord {\uparrow }f(x):x\in T\}\). Going forward, we will blur the distinction between the function f and the open cover \(\mathcal {U}_f\), and speak simply of the cover f. We will also consider \(\mathcal {U}_f\) for \(f\in \prod _{x\in X}[I(x)]^{<\omega }\), where \(X\subseteq T\) (of course, \(\mathcal {U}_f\) might not cover T).
Note that covers of this kind have the following important property:
Lemma 3.4
Let T be a tree and \(f\in \prod _{x\in T}[I(x)]^{<\omega }\). The following are equivalent:
-
(1)
f has a countable subcover.
-
(2)
There is a limit ordinal \(\alpha <\omega _1\) such that \(f\mathord {\upharpoonright }(T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha )\) covers T.
-
(3)
There is an ordinal \(\alpha <\omega _1\) such that for every \(x\in {T}_\alpha \) there is some \(y\in T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \) such that \(x\in \mathord {\uparrow }y\setminus \mathord {\uparrow }f(y)\).
Proof
Trivial.\(\square \)
Definition 3.5
Let T be an \(\aleph _1\)-tree and \(f\in \prod _{x\in T} [I(x)]^{<\omega }\). We say that a point \(x\in T\) is safe (for f) if and only if for all \(y<x\), \(x\in \mathord {\uparrow }f(y)\).
An immediate consequence of the definition is:
Lemma 3.6
Let T be an \(\aleph _1\)-tree and \(f\in \prod _{x\in T} [I(x)]^{<\omega }\). If \(x\in T\) is safe, then so is every \(y<x\). Also, if \(z\in I(x)\) (with x safe), then z is safe if and only if \(z\in f(x)\).
Proof
Trivial.\(\square \)
The key property of safe points is the following:
Lemma 3.7
Let T be an infinitely splitting \(\aleph _1\)-tree and \(f\in \prod _{x\in T}[I(x)]^{<\omega }\). The following are equivalent:
-
(1)
f has no countable subcover.
-
(2)
For every \(\alpha <\omega _1\) there is a safe point of height \(\alpha \).
-
(3)
The set \(\{\textrm{ht}(x):x\text { is safe}\}\) is unbounded in \(\omega _1\).
Proof
\((1)\Rightarrow (2)\): Fix \(\alpha <\omega _1\). By Lemma 3.4, there is some \(x\in {T}_\alpha \) such that for all \(y\in T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \), \(x\not \in \mathord {\uparrow }y\setminus \mathord {\uparrow }f(y)\). In particular, if \(y<x\), \(x\in \mathord {\uparrow }f(y)\), so x is safe.
\((2)\Rightarrow (3)\): Trivial.
\((3)\Rightarrow (1)\): Suppose towards a contradiction that f has a countable subcover. By Lemma 3.4, there is some limit \(\gamma <\omega _1\) such that \(f\mathord {\upharpoonright }(T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\gamma )\) covers T. Choose a safe point x with \(\gamma <\textrm{ht}(x)\). Let \(y\in T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\gamma \). If \(y\not < x\), then obviously \(x\not \in \mathord {\uparrow }y{\setminus } \mathord {\uparrow }f(y)\). If \(y<x\), the safety of x implies that \(x\in \mathord {\uparrow }f(y)\), so \(x\not \in \mathord {\uparrow }y\setminus \mathord {\uparrow }f(y)\). In either case, \(x\not \in \bigcup \mathcal {U}_{f\mathord {\upharpoonright }(T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\gamma )}=T\), contradiction.\(\square \)
Recall that a subtree of a tree is a downwards closed subset. Note that, if S is a subtree of T and \(\alpha <\textrm{ht}(T)\), then \(S_\alpha =S\cap T_\alpha \). Also, if \(x\in S\), then \(I_S(x)=I_T(x)\cap S\).
Theorem 3.8
Let T be an infinitely splitting \(\aleph _1\)-tree. Then T is Lindelöf if and only if every finitely splitting subtree of T is countable.
Proof
\(\Rightarrow )\) Let \(S\subseteq T\) be a finitely branching subtree of T. Note that the subspace topology on S is just the fine wedge topology of S as a tree. Since S is finitely splitting, it is closed and discrete (see Remark 3.1), hence T cannot be Lindelöf.
\(\Leftarrow \)) Let f code a cover with no countable subcover. Let S be the set of points of S which are safe for f. It is clear that S is a subtree of T. Given \(x\in S\), we see that \(I_{S}(x)=f(x)\), so S is finitely splitting. Since f has no countable subcover, \(\textrm{ht}(S)=\aleph _1\).\(\square \)
Corollary 3.9
Every Lindelöf tree is Aronszajn.
Proof
Let T be a Lindelöf tree and \(b\subseteq T\) a branch. Then \(\mathord {\downarrow }b\) is a finitely splitting subtree of T, hence countable by Theorem 3.8.\(\square \)
Remark 3.10
Recall that, if there is a Suslin tree, then there is one that is infinitely splitting, see [4, Lemma 9.13].
Theorem 3.11
Let T be an infinitely splitting Suslin tree. Then T is Lindeöf.
Proof
Suppose that S is a finitely splitting subtree of T with height \(\aleph _1\). Fix a sequence \({\langle {x_\alpha :\alpha <\omega _1}\rangle }\) with \(x_\alpha \in S_\alpha \). For each \(\alpha <\omega _1\), choose \(y_\alpha \in I_T(x_\alpha ){\setminus } S\). We show that \(\{y_\alpha :\alpha <\omega _1\}\) is an antichain. Indeed, if \(\alpha <\beta \) and \(y_\alpha <y_\beta \), then \(y_\alpha \le x_\beta \) because \(y_\beta \in I_T(x_\beta )\). But then \(y_\alpha \in S\), contradiction.
We have shown that every finitely splitting subtree of T is countable. By 3.8, T is Lindelöf.\(\square \)
4 Examples of Lindelöf and non-Lindelöf trees
If s and t are two functions with domain \(\alpha \), we let \(\Delta (s,t):=\{\xi <\alpha :s(\xi )\ne t(\xi )\}\). We write \(s=^*t\) if and only if \(\Delta (s,t)\) is finite.
We shall say that \({\langle {e_\alpha :\alpha <\omega _1}\rangle }\) is a coherent sequence of injections if \(e_\alpha :\alpha \rightarrow \omega \) is injective and \(e_\alpha =^*e_\beta \mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \) for all \(\alpha ,\beta <\omega _1\). Note that each \(e_\alpha \) must have coinfinite range. Going forward, we shall speak simply of coherent sequences, which in the literature usually refers to finite to one functions. Let
It is clear that \(T^{\textbf{e}}\) is an infinitely splitting Aronszajn tree.
Our next goal is to construct a non-Lindelöf Aronszajn tree. The idea is to build a finitely splitting Aronszajn tree, and then make \(\aleph _0\) many new nodes “sprout" at each node, producing a larger, infinitely splitting tree. The constructions of Aronszajn trees that we’re familiar with all produce infinitely splitting trees, so our first task is to build a finitely splitting one.
Recall that a tree if splitting if every node has at least two distinct immediate successors.
Lemma 4.1
There is a splitting subtree of \(2^{<\omega _1}\) which is Aronszajn.
Proof
Fix a coherent sequence \(\textbf{e}\) and a bijection \(f:\omega _1\times \omega \rightarrow \omega _1\) such that for every limit ordinal \(\gamma <\omega _1\), \(f[\gamma \times \omega ]=\gamma \). Put \(\Gamma =\lim (\omega _1)\cup \{0\}\). Define \(x_\alpha \in 2^\alpha \) for \(\alpha \in \Gamma \) by \(x_\alpha =\chi _{f[e_\alpha ]}\), where \(\chi _A\) denotes the characteristic function of A. This makes sense because \(f[e_\alpha ]\subseteq \alpha \).
Claim
If \(\alpha ,\beta \in \Gamma \) and \(\alpha <\beta \) then \(x_\alpha =^* x_\beta \mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \).
Proof of Claim
For readability, we extend our \(\Delta (s,t)\) notation to allow functions with different domains. More precisely, if \(\textrm{dom}(s)\le \textrm{dom}(t)\), we write \(\Delta (s,t)\) for \(\Delta (s,t\mathord {\upharpoonright }\textrm{dom}(s))\).
If \(\alpha =0\) everything is trivial so we assume that \(\alpha \ge \omega \). Fix \(\eta \in \Delta (x_\alpha ,x_\beta )\), so \(x_\alpha (\eta )\ne x_\beta (\eta )\). Since \(f[\alpha \times \omega ]=\alpha \), there exist unique \(\xi <\alpha \) and \(n\in \omega \) with \(f(\xi ,n)=\eta \).
Since \(x_\alpha (\eta )\ne x_\beta (\eta )\), there are two possibilities: \(\eta \in f[e_\alpha ]\setminus f[e_\beta ]\) or \(\eta \in f[e_\beta ]{\setminus } f[e_\alpha ]\). We consider the two cases separately:
-
1.
Suppose that \(\eta \in f[e_\alpha ]\setminus f[e_\beta ]\). Then \(e_\alpha (\xi )=n\) but \(e_\beta (\xi )\ne n\), so \(\xi \in \Delta (e_\alpha ,e_\beta )\) and \(\eta =f(\xi ,e_\alpha (\xi ))\).
-
2.
Suppose that \(\eta \in f[e_\beta ]\setminus f[e_\alpha ]\). Then \(e_\beta (\xi )=n\) but \(e_\alpha (\xi )\ne n\), so \(\xi \in \Delta (e_\alpha ,e_\beta )\) and \(\eta =f(\xi ,e_\beta (\xi ))\).
We have therefore established that
Since \(\textbf{e}\) is coherent, the union on the right is finite, hence \(\Delta (x_\alpha ,x_\beta )\) is finite too.
Given \(\alpha <\omega _1\), let \(\gamma _\alpha \) be the unique ordinal in \(\Gamma \) such that \(\gamma _\alpha \le \alpha <\gamma _\alpha +\omega \). Note that \(\alpha \in \Gamma \) if and only if \(\alpha = \gamma _\alpha \). Define
By the claim, T is a subtree of \(2^{<\omega _1}\). Indeed, if \(x\in 2^\alpha \) and \(y\in T\cap 2^\beta \) satisfy \(x\subseteq y\), then \(\gamma _\alpha \le \gamma _\beta \), so \(x\mathord {\upharpoonright }\gamma _\alpha =(y\mathord {\upharpoonright }\gamma _\beta )\mathord {\upharpoonright }\gamma _\alpha =^*x_{\gamma _\beta }\mathord {\upharpoonright }\gamma _\alpha =^* x_{\gamma _\alpha }\), where the last \(=^*\) follows from the claim. The fact that T has countable levels is immediate from the claim. As \(x_\alpha \in T_\alpha \) for every \(\alpha \in \Gamma \), we see that T has height \(\omega _1\), and so T is an \(\aleph _1\)-tree.
We point out that that, if \(x\in T\), then \(x^\frown {\langle {0}\rangle },x^\frown {\langle {1}\rangle }\in T\), because \(\gamma _\alpha =\gamma _{\alpha +1}\) for every \(\alpha <\omega _1\).
To see that T is Aronszajn, assume towards a contradiction that \({\langle {y_\alpha :\alpha <\omega _1}\rangle }\) is a branch through T, so in particular \(y_\alpha =^*x_\alpha \) for every \(\alpha \in \lim (\omega _1)\). Find \(\eta _\alpha <\alpha \) for each \(\alpha \in \lim (\omega _1)\) so that \(\Delta (y_\alpha ,x_\alpha )\subseteq \eta _\alpha \). Since \(\alpha \mapsto \eta _\alpha \) is regressive, by Fodor’s Lemma there is some stationary set \(E\subseteq \lim (\omega _1)\) and some \(\eta <\omega _1\) such that \(\eta _\alpha =\eta \) for every \(\alpha \in E\). Since \(|T_\eta |\le \aleph _0\), we may find \(E'\subseteq E\) stationary and \(x,y\in 2^\eta \) such that \(y_\alpha \mathord {\upharpoonright }\eta =y\) and \(x_\alpha \mathord {\upharpoonright }\eta =x\) for every \(\alpha \in E'\). If \(\alpha ,\beta \in E'\), \(\alpha <\beta \),
by the choice of \(\eta \). Since \(x_\alpha \mathord {\upharpoonright }\eta =x=x_\beta \mathord {\upharpoonright }\eta \), it follows that \(x_\alpha =x_\beta \mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \). Finally, if \(\xi <\alpha \) and \(n:=e_\alpha (\xi )\), then \(x_\alpha (f(\xi ,n))=1\), so \(x_\beta (f(\xi ,n))=1\), so \(f(\xi ,n)\in f[e_\beta ]\), so \(e_\beta (\xi )=n\). We have thus shown that \({\langle {e_\alpha :\alpha \in E'}\rangle }\) is a chain, which is absurd because \(E'\) is uncountable.\(\square \)
Lemma 4.2
There is an infinitely splitting Aronszajn tree with a finitely splitting subtree of height \(\aleph _1\).
Proof
Let \(\textbf{e}\) be a coherent sequence and let \(T\subseteq 2^{<\omega _1}\) be the tree constructed from \(\textbf{e}\) in Lemma 4.1. We recursively define a tree \(U\subseteq \omega ^{<\omega _1}\) level by level, starting with \(U_0=\{\emptyset \}\). For successor stages, we let \(U_{\alpha +1}=\{u^\smallfrown {\langle {n}\rangle }: u\in U_\alpha \wedge n\in \omega \}\). If \(\alpha <\omega _1\) is a limit ordinal, we let \(U_\alpha =\{u\cup t\mathord {\upharpoonright }[\textrm{dom}(u),\alpha ):u\in U\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \wedge t \in T_\alpha \}\). An easy induction shows that \(U_\alpha \) is countable and that \(T_\alpha \subseteq U_\alpha \) for every \(\alpha \).
Claim1
If \(\beta <\alpha \), \(t\in T_\alpha \) and \(u\in U_\beta \), then \(u\cup t\mathord {\upharpoonright }[\beta ,\alpha )\in U_\alpha \).
Proof of Claim 1
By induction on \(\alpha \):
-
If \(\alpha =0\), then it’s obvious.
-
Suppose that \(\alpha \) is a successor ordinal, say \(\alpha =\gamma +1\). Then \( u \cup (t\mathord {\upharpoonright }[\beta ,\alpha ) )= (u\cup t\mathord {\upharpoonright }[\beta ,\gamma ))^\smallfrown {\langle {t(\gamma )}\rangle } \) which belongs to \(U_\alpha \) by the inductive hypothesis and the definition of \(U_\alpha \).
-
If \(\alpha \) is a limit ordinal, this is immediate from the definition of \(U_\alpha \).
Claim2
If \(\alpha <\omega _1\), \(\beta <\alpha \) and \(v\in U_\alpha \), then \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }\beta \in U\).
Proof of Claim 2
By induction on \(\alpha \):
-
If \(\alpha =0\) then it’s vacuously true.
-
Suppose that \(\alpha \) is a successor ordinal, say \(\alpha =\gamma +1\). Fix \(v\in U_\alpha \), so \(v=u^\smallfrown {\langle {n}\rangle }\) for some \(u\in U_{\gamma }\) and \(n\in \omega \). Let \(\beta <\alpha \). If \(\beta =\gamma \), then \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }\beta =u\in U\) as desired. If \(\beta <\gamma \), then \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }\beta =u\mathord {\upharpoonright }\beta \in U\) by the inductive hypothesis applied to \(\gamma \).
-
Suppose that \(\alpha \) is a limit ordinal and let \(v\in U_\alpha \), say \(v=u\cup (t\mathord {\upharpoonright }[\textrm{dom}(u),\alpha ))\), where \(u\in U_\gamma \), \(\gamma <\alpha \), and \(t\in T\). Let \(\beta <\alpha \). If \(\beta =\gamma \), then \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }\beta =u\in U_\beta \). If \(\beta <\gamma \), then \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }\beta =u\mathord {\upharpoonright }\beta \in U\) by the inductive hypothesis applied to \(\gamma \). If \(\gamma <\beta \), then \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }\beta = u\cup (t\mathord {\upharpoonright }[\textrm{dom}(u),\beta ))\). We now induct on \(\beta \). If \(\beta \) is a limit ordinal, then \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }\beta \in U_\beta \) by definition of \(U_\beta \). If \(\beta \) is a successor ordinal, say \(\beta =\delta +1\), then \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }\beta = (u\cup t\mathord {\upharpoonright }[\textrm{dom}(u),\delta ))^\smallfrown {\langle {t(\delta )}\rangle } \). By Claim 1, \( u\cup t\mathord {\upharpoonright }[\textrm{dom}(u),\delta ) \in U_\delta \), and so \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }\beta \in U_\beta \) by definition of \(U_\beta \).
To see that U is Aronszajn, suppose towards a contradiction that b is a cofinal branch through U. Let \(x_\alpha \) be the \( \alpha ^\text {th}\) point of b. For each limit ordinal \(\alpha <\omega _1\), there exist \(u_\alpha <x_\alpha \) and \(t_\alpha \in T_\alpha \) such that \(x_\alpha =u_\alpha \cup t_\alpha \mathord {\upharpoonright }[\textrm{dom}(u_\alpha ),\alpha )\). Define \(f:\lim (\omega _1)\rightarrow \omega _1\) by \(f(\alpha )=\textrm{dom}(u_\alpha )\). Since f is regressive, we may find a stationary set \(\Gamma \subseteq \lim (\omega _1)\) and some \(\eta <\omega _1\) such that \(f``\Gamma =\{\eta \}\). As \(|T_\eta |\le \aleph _0\), we may assume, by shrinking \(\Gamma \) if necessary, that there is some \(t\in T_\eta \) such that \(t=t_\alpha \mathord {\upharpoonright }\eta \) for all \(\alpha \in \Gamma \). If \(\alpha ,\beta \in \Gamma \), \(\alpha <\beta \), then \(t_\alpha \mathord {\upharpoonright }[\eta ,\alpha )=x_\alpha \mathord {\upharpoonright }[\eta ,\alpha )=x_\beta \mathord {\upharpoonright }[\eta ,\alpha )=t_\beta \mathord {\upharpoonright }[\eta ,\alpha )\) by our choice of \(\eta \). But then \(t_\alpha =t_\beta \mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \) because they both agree with t below \(\eta \). This means that \({\langle {t_\alpha :\alpha \in \Gamma }\rangle }\) is an uncountable chain in T, contradicting that T is Aronszajn.\(\square \)
Corollary 4.3
There is a non-Lindelöf Aronszajn tree.
Proof
Apply lemmas 4.1 and 4.2 to obtain an infinitely splitting Aronszajn tree T with a finitely splitting subtree of uncountable height. Then T is not Lindelöf by Theorem 3.8.\(\square \)
Recall that Jensen’s diamond principle, denoted \(\diamondsuit \), asserts the existence of a sequence \({\langle {A_\alpha :\alpha <\omega _1}\rangle }\) such that \(A_\alpha \subseteq \alpha \) and for every \(A\subseteq \omega _1\) there exist stationarily many \(\alpha <\omega _1\) with \(A\cap \alpha =A_\alpha \). We shall need to modify the \(\diamondsuit \)-sequence so that it “guesses" functions \(\omega _1\rightarrow [\omega _1]^{<\omega }\).
Lemma 4.4
The principle \(\diamondsuit \) holds if and only if there is a sequence \({\langle {f_\alpha :\alpha <\omega _1}\rangle }\) such that \(f_\alpha :\alpha \rightarrow [\alpha ]^{<\omega }\) and for every \(f:\omega _1\rightarrow [\omega _1]^{<\omega }\) the set \(\{\alpha :f\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha =f_\alpha \}\) is stationary.
The proof is a standard coding argument, and we omit it.
A sequence \({\langle {f_\alpha :\alpha <\omega _1}\rangle }\) of the kind appearing in the statement of Lemma 4.4 will also be referred to as a \(\diamondsuit \)-sequence.
Recall that an \(\aleph _1\)-tree is special if and only if it can be written as a countable union of antichains. Equivalently, T is special if and only if there is an order preserving map \(T\rightarrow \mathbb {Q}\), see [6, Lemma III.5.17].
Theorem 4.5
If \(\diamondsuit \) holds, then there is a special Lindelöf tree.
Proof
We construct a normal, infinitely splitting T level by level, together with a specializing function \(\varphi :T\rightarrow \mathbb {Q}\). To make sure that \(\varphi \) can be extended at limit stages, we require that
holds for every \(\alpha <\omega _1\). The construction will also depend on a fixed \(\diamondsuit \) sequence \({\langle {f_\alpha :\alpha <\omega _1}\rangle }\) such that \(f_\alpha :\alpha \rightarrow [\alpha ]^{<\omega }\) and, for every \(f:\omega _1\rightarrow [\omega _1]^{<\omega }\), the set \(\{\alpha <\omega _1:f\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha =f_\alpha \}\) is stationary. Such a sequence of functions exists by Lemma 4.4.
The underlying set of the tree will be \(\omega _1\), with \(T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha =\omega \alpha \) and \({T}_\alpha =[\omega \alpha ,\omega (\alpha +1))\) for \(\alpha >\omega \). Let 0 be the root of T. For the successor step, given a node at level \(\alpha \) we put \(\aleph _0\) many nodes immediately above x and let \(\varphi \mathord {\upharpoonright }I(x)\) be a bijection between I(x) and \(\mathbb {Q}\cap (\varphi (x),\infty )\). Note that normality and (*) continue to hold.
Suppose now that \(\alpha <\omega _1\) is a limit ordinal and we’ve constructed \(T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \) and \(\varphi \mathord {\upharpoonright }T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \). List the set \(\{(x,q)\in T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \times \mathbb {Q}:\varphi (x)<q\}\) as \(\{(x_k,q_k):k\in \omega \}\). The construction splits into two cases.
Case 1: \(\omega \alpha >\alpha \). Fix \(k\in \omega \). By normality and (*), we can choose a branch \(b_k\) with least element \(x_k\) such that the heights of members of \(b_k\) converge to \(\alpha \) and \(\sup (\varphi ``b_k)=q_k\). Now put a node above \(b_k\) and let \(\varphi \) take the value \(q_k\) at this node.
Case 2: \(\omega \alpha =\alpha \). Fix \(k\in \omega \). Choose a cofinal branch \(b_k\subseteq T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \) satisfying the following properties:
-
(i)
\(x_k\in b_k\),
-
(ii)
\(\sup (\varphi ``b_k)=q_k\),
-
(iii)
the unique point on \(b_k\) immediately above \(x_k\) does not belong to \(f_\alpha (x_k)\).
To achieve this, use that, by our construction at successor stages, \(\varphi \) maps \(I(x_k)\) onto \(\mathbb {Q}\cap (\varphi (x_k),\infty )\) to find a point \(z_k\in I(x_k){\setminus } f_\alpha (x_k)\) with \(\varphi (z_k) < q_k\). Then construct \(b_k\) by repeatedly applying \((*)\) and taking a downwards closure. Finally, put a node above \(b_k\) on level \(\alpha \) and let \(\varphi \) take the value \(q_k\) at this node. This completes the construction of T.
It is obvious that \(\varphi \) is a specializing function for T. To see that T is Lindelöf, consider a basic cover \(f\in \prod _{x\in T}[I(x)]^{<\omega }\). Pick \(\alpha <\omega _1\) limit such that \(\omega \cdot \alpha =\alpha \) and \(f\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha =f_\alpha \), so that \(f\mathord {\upharpoonright }(T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha )=f_\alpha \).
The key observation is that every node at level \(\alpha \) is in \(\mathord {\uparrow }y\setminus \bigcup _{z\in f_\alpha (y)}\mathord {\uparrow }z\) for some \(y\in T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \). By Lemma 3.4, \(f_\alpha \) covers T, hence so does \(f\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \), and we’re done.\(\square \)
Corollary 4.6
If \(\diamondsuit \) holds, then there is a Lindelöf tree that is not Suslin.
Proof
Assume \(\diamondsuit \) holds. By Theorem 4.5, there is a special Lindelöf tree. But special trees can never be Suslin.\(\square \)
So, under \(\diamondsuit \), we have strict inclusion of our classes of trees:
5 Adding subtrees
In this section, we address the following question: given an infinitely splitting Aronszajn tree T, can we find a poset \(\mathbb {P}\) such that \(\Vdash _\mathbb {P}\) T is a non-Lindelöf Aronszajn tree? In other words, \(\mathbb {P}\) forces the existence of an uncountable finitely splitting subtree of T but at the same time adds no uncountable branches to T.
Definition 5.1
Given an infinitely splitting \(\aleph _1\)-tree T, we let \(\mathbb {P}_T\) be the following poset: conditions are finite functions with \(p\in \prod _{x\in F}[I(x)]^{<\omega }\), where \(F\in [T]^{<\omega }\), such that \(\emptyset \not \in \textrm{ran}(p)\) and which satisfy the following property:
The order on \(\mathbb {P}_T\) is \(p\le q \iff p\supseteq q\).
The idea is that a condition is a promise that a certain subtree will be finitely splitting at each point of the condition’s domain.
Lemma 5.2
(Baumgartner) Let T be a tree with no uncountable branches. Suppose that \(\mathscr {A}\) is an uncountable collection of pairwise disjoint non-empty finite subsets of T. Then there exist \(a,b\in \mathscr {A}\) such that for all \(x\in a\) and \(y\in b\), \(x\perp y\).
For a proof, see [6, Lemma III.5.18].
Lemma 5.3
Let T be an Aronszajn tree. Then \(\mathbb {P}_T\) has the ccc.
Proof
Let \({\langle {p_\alpha :\alpha <\omega _1}\rangle }\subseteq \mathbb {P}_T\). Letting \(d_\alpha =\textrm{dom}(p_\alpha )\) and thinning out if necessary, we may assume without loss of generality that \(\{d_\alpha :\alpha <\omega _1\}\) forms a \(\Delta \)-system with root R and that \(\alpha<\beta <\omega _1\) implies \(p_\alpha \mathord {\upharpoonright }R=p_\beta \mathord {\upharpoonright }R\). Apply Lemma 5.2 to find \(\alpha<\beta <\omega _1\) such that \(x\perp y\) for all \(x\in d_\alpha {\setminus } R\) and \(y\in d_\beta {\setminus } R\). Let \(r=p_\alpha \cup p_\beta \). Then r is a condition, because the only way two points in its domain are comparable is if they both belong to either \(d_\alpha \) or \(d_\beta \), hence \((\dagger )\) holds. Since \(r\le p_\alpha ,p_\beta \), we are done.\(\square \)
Lemma 5.4
Let T be an infinitely splitting Aronszajn tree and \(\dot{S}\) a \(\mathbb {P}_T\) name for the set \(\bigcup _{p\in \dot{G}}\textrm{dom}(p)\), where \(\dot{G}\) is a \(\mathbb {P}_T\)-name for the generic filter.
-
(i)
For every \(p\in \mathbb {P}_T\), every \(y\in \textrm{dom}(p)\) and every \(x\in T\), if \(x<y\), then \(p\Vdash x\in \dot{S}\).
-
(ii)
\(\Vdash \dot{S}\) is downwards closed.
-
(iii)
For all \(p\in \mathbb {P}_T\) and all \(x\in \textrm{dom}(p)\), \(p\Vdash I_{\dot{S}}(x)\subseteq p(x)\).
-
(iv)
For all \(p\in \mathbb {P}_T\) and all \(x\in \textrm{dom}(p)\), \(p\Vdash p(x)\subseteq \dot{S}\).
-
(v)
For all \(\alpha <\omega _1\), the set \(\{p\in \mathbb {P}_T:\exists x\in \textrm{dom}(p)(\textrm{ht}(x)\ge \alpha )\}\) is dense in \(\mathbb {P}_T\).
Proof
Write \(\mathbb {P}=\mathbb {P}_T\) to simplify the notation.
-
(i)
It suffices to show that the set \(\{r\in \mathbb {P}: x\in \textrm{dom}(r)\}\) is dense below p. Fix \(q\le p\) with \(x\not \in \textrm{dom}(q)\). Let \(E=\{t\in \textrm{dom}(q):x<t\}\). Since \(y\in E\), \(E\ne \emptyset \). Define a function r with domain \(\textrm{dom}(q)\cup \{x\}\) by \(r\mathord {\upharpoonright }\textrm{dom}(q)=q\) and \(r(x)=\{t\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(x)+1):t\in E\}\). Since \(E\ne \emptyset \), \(r(x)\ne \emptyset \). Obviously, \(q\subseteq r\). We check that r is a condition. Fix \(u,v\in \textrm{dom}(r)\) with \(u<v\).
-
If \(u,v\in \textrm{dom}(q)\), then \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)\in q(u)=r(u)\).
-
If \(u=x\), then \(v\in E\), so \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)\in r(x)\) by definition of r(x).
-
If \(v=x\), then \(u<y\) by \(x<y\), therefore
$$\begin{aligned} v\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)&=x\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)\\&= y\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u+1))\in q(u) =r(u). \end{aligned}$$
So, in every case, \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)\in r(u)\), and therefore r is a condition.
-
-
(ii)
Let G is \({\mathbb {P}}\)-generic over V and \(y\in S=\dot{S}_G\). Suppose \(x<y\). Fix \(p\in G\) with \(y\in \textrm{dom}(p)\). By (i), we can find \(q\in G\) with \(x\in \textrm{dom}(p)\). Then \(x\in S\).
-
(iii)
Let \(G\ni p\) be \({\mathbb {P}}\)-generic over V and suppose \(y\in I_{S}(x)\), where \(S=\dot{S}_G\). Since \(y\in S\), there exists \(q\in G\) with \(y\in \textrm{dom}(q)\). Choose \(r\in G\) with \(r\le p,q\). Then \(x,y\in \textrm{dom}(r)\) and \(x<y\), so
$$\begin{aligned} y=y\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(x)+1)\in r(x)=p(x) \end{aligned}$$because r is a condition.
-
(iv)
Fix \(y\in p(x)\). As in (i), it suffices to argue that \(\{r\in \mathbb {P}:y\in \textrm{dom}(r)\}\) is dense below p. Let \(q\le p\) with \(y\not \in \textrm{dom}(q)\) and let \(E=\{t\in \textrm{dom}(q):y<t\}\). Case 1: \(E\ne \emptyset \). This is as in (i): define r by \(r\mathord {\upharpoonright }\textrm{dom}(q)=q\) and \(r(y)=\{t\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(y)+1):t\in E\}\). The verification that r is a condition is exactly the same as in the proof of (i). Case 2: \(E=\emptyset \). Let a be any finite non-empty subset of \(I_T(y)\) and let \(r=q\cup \{(y,a)\}\). It is enough to show that r is a condition. Fix \(u,v\in \textrm{dom}(r)\) with \(u<v\).
-
If \(u,v\in \textrm{dom}(q)\), then \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)\in q(u)=r(u)\).
-
If \(u=y\), then \(v\in \textrm{dom}(q)\), so \(v\in E\), which contradicts \(E=\emptyset \).
-
If \(v=y\), then \(u\le x\) because \(y\in I_T(x)\). We now distinguish two cases. If \(u=x\), then
$$\begin{aligned} v\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)&= y\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)\\&=y\in p(x)= q(x)=r(x)=r(u). \end{aligned}$$If \(u<x\), then \(u\in \textrm{dom}(q)\) and \(x\in \textrm{dom}(p)\subseteq \textrm{dom}(q)\), so
$$\begin{aligned} v\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)&= y\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1) = x\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)\in q(u)=r(u). \end{aligned}$$
In every case, \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)\in r(u)\), and so r is a condition.
-
-
(v)
Fix \(p\in \mathbb {P}\). We may assume that \(\textrm{dom}(p)\subseteq T\mathord {\upharpoonright }\alpha \). Since \(\emptyset \not \in \textrm{ran}(p)\), we can define \(\gamma =\max \{\textrm{ht}(y):y\in \bigcup \textrm{ran}(p)\}\). Note that \(\gamma =\beta +1\) for some \(\beta \). Fix \(y\in \bigcup \textrm{ran}(p)\) with \(\textrm{ht}(y)=\beta +1\). By maximality, \(y\not \in \textrm{dom}(p)\). Case 1: \(\beta +1=\alpha \). By the proof of (v), there exists \(q\le p\) with \(y\in \textrm{dom}(p)\), and we are done. Case 2: \(\beta +1<\alpha \) Since T is normal, there exists \(z\in T_\alpha \) with \(y<z\). Let a be any finite non-empty subset of I(z) and let \(q=p\cup \{(z,a)\}\). We check that q is a condition.
-
If \(u,v\in \textrm{dom}(p)\), then it is easy.
-
If \(u=z\), then \(v\in \textrm{dom}(p)\). But \(v>u\), so \(\textrm{ht}(v)>\alpha >\gamma \), contradiction.
-
If \(v=z\), then \(\textrm{ht}(u)\le \textrm{ht}(x)\), where x is the immediate predecessor of y. Since T is a tree, \(u\le x\). If \(u=x\), then by \(z>y\) we infer that
$$\begin{aligned} v\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(x)+1)=y\in p(x)=q(x). \end{aligned}$$If \(u<x\), then
$$\begin{aligned} v\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)=x\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)=p(u)=r(u) \end{aligned}$$
In every case, \(v\mathord {\upharpoonright }(\textrm{ht}(u)+1)\in r(u)\), and so r is a condition.
-
\(\square \)
Theorem 5.5
Let T be an infinitely splitting Aronszajn tree and \(\dot{S}\) a \(\mathbb {P}_T\) name for the set \(\bigcup _{p\in \dot{G}}\textrm{dom}(p)\), where \(\dot{G}\) is a \(\mathbb {P}_T\)-name for the generic filter. Then \(\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_T}``\dot{S}\) is an uncountable finitely splitting subtree of T".
Proof
By Lemma 5.3, \(\mathbb {P}_T\) preserves cardinals. By parts (ii),(iii) and (v) of Lemma 5.4, it is forced by \(\mathbb {P}_T\) that \(\dot{S}\) is an uncountable finitely splitting subtree of T.\(\square \)
Since the forcing \(\mathbb {P}_T\) is only ccc and not obviously Knaster, it is unclear whether T remains Aronszajn in the \(\mathbb {P}_T\)-extension. To deal with this issue, we first do some preliminary forcing.
Definition 5.6
(Baumgartner) If T is a tree, then \({\mathbb {S}}_T\) is the poset of finite order preserving partial functions from T into \(\mathbb {Q}\) (the set of rational numbers), ordered by inclusion.
Theorem 5.7
(Baumgartner) Let T be an Aronszajn tree. Then
-
(1)
\({\mathbb {S}}_T\) has the ccc.
-
(2)
\(\Vdash _{{\mathbb {S}}_T} T\) is special.
For a proof, see [6, Lemma III.5.19].
Theorem 5.8
Let T be an Aronszajn tree. Then \(\mathbb {P}_T\) adds no cofinal branches to T. Therefore, \(\mathbb {P}_T\) forces that T is a non-Lindelöf Aronszajn tree.
Proof
Let G be \(\mathbb {P}_T\)-generic over V. Suppose towards a contradiction that T is not an Aronszajn tree in V[G]. Note that the definitions of \(\mathbb {S}_T\) and \(\mathbb {P}_T\) are both absolute, so the two posets are the same whether computed in V or in any outer model. Let H be \(\mathbb {S}_T\)-generic over V[G]. By the Product Lemma, \(V[G][H]=V[H][G]\) and G is \(\mathbb {P}_T\)-generic over V[H]. In V, T has no uncountable branches, so \(\mathbb {S}_T\) is ccc, and therefore T is special in V[H]. In particular, T is an Aronszajn tree in V[H], hence \(\mathbb {P}_T\) is ccc in V[H]. But if T is special then it remains special in any \(\aleph _1\)-preserving extension, in particular T is special in V[H][G]. This contradicts the assumption that there is a cofinal branch through T in V[G].
The second assertion in the theorem statement is an immediate consequence of the first and Theorem 5.5.\(\square \)
Corollary 5.9
Suppose that \(\textsf{MA}_{\aleph _1}\) holds. Then there are no Lindelöf trees.
Proof
Given an Aronszajn tree T, we only need to meet \(\aleph _1\)-many dense sets of \(\mathbb {P}_T\) to obtain an uncountable finitely splitting subtree of T, namely those in Lemma 5.4(vi).\(\square \)
6 Open questions
-
(1)
Suppose \(\lambda <\mu \) are infinite cardinals. Is it consistent, modulo large cardinals, that there exists a cardinal \(\kappa \le \lambda \) which is \(\lambda \)-square compact but not \(\mu \)-square compact?
-
(2)
For which pairs of infinite cardinals \(\kappa ,\lambda \) with \(\kappa <\lambda \) can one find a Hausdorff \(\kappa \)-compact space of weight \(\lambda \)?
-
(3)
Does \(\mathsf ZFC\) prove the existence of a non-Lindelöf special tree?
-
(4)
Is the topological square of a Lindelöf tree Lindelöf?
Notes
We caution the reader that, in Nyikos’ survey, X being \(\omega _1\)-compact is used to mean a different property than being Lindelöf.
References
Buhagiar, D., Džamonja, M.: Square compactness and the filter extension property. Fundam. Math. 252(3), 325–342 (2021). https://doi.org/10.4064/fm787-4-2020
Comfort, W.W., Negrepontis, S.: The theory of ultrafilters. Vol. B and 211. Die Grundlehren der mathematischen Wissenschaften. Springer-Verlag, New York-Heidelberg (1974)
Hajnal, A., Juhász, I.: On square-compact cardinals Periodica Mathematica Hungarica. J. János Bolyai Math. Soc. 3(3–4), 285–288 (1973). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02018595
Jech, T.: Set theory The third millennium edition revised and expanded Springer Monographs in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, Berlin (2003)
Keisler, H.J., Tarski, A.: From accessible to inaccessible cardinals. Results holding for all accessible cardinal numbers and the problem of their extension to inaccessible ones Polska Akademia Nauk. Fundamenta Mathematicae 53, 225–308 (1963). https://doi.org/10.4064/fm-53-3-225-308
Kunen, K.: Set theory. Vol. 34. Studies in Logic (London). College Publications, London, 2011. isbn: 978-1-84890-050-9
Kunen, K., Vaughan, J.E., eds. Handbook of set-theoretic topology. North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam, 1984. isbn: 978-0-444-86580- 9
Mycielski, J.: Two remarks on Tychonoff’s product theorem. In: Bulletin de l’Académie Polonaise des Sciences. Série des Sciences Mathématiques, Astronomiques et Physiques 12 (1964), pp. 439–441
Nyikos, R.J.: Various topologies on trees. In: Proceedings of the Tennessee Topology Conference (Nashville, TN, 1996). World Sci. Publ., River Edge, NJ, 1997, pp. 167–198
J Arthur Seebach and Lynn AS. Counterexamples in topology. Vol. 18. Springer, 1978
Acknowledgements
The author thanks the referee for their careful reading and insightful comments.
Funding
Open Access funding provided by Carnegie Mellon University.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Contributions
The author confirms sole responsibility for the contents of this paper.
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Conflict of interest
The authors declare no competing interests.
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
The results of this paper will form a part of the author’s PhD thesis written under the supervision of James Cummings, to whom the author would like to express his gratitude.
Rights and permissions
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
About this article
Cite this article
Marun, P.E. Square compactness and Lindelöf trees. Arch. Math. Logic 63, 741–757 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00153-024-00918-5
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00153-024-00918-5