Abstract
Feedback Turing machines are Turing machines which can query a halting oracle which has information on the convergence or divergence of feedback computations. To avoid a contradiction by diagonalization, feedback Turing machines have two ways of not converging: they can diverge as standard Turing machines, or they can freeze. A natural question to ask is: what about feedback Turing machines which can ask if computations of the same type converge, diverge, or freeze? We define \(\alpha \)th order feedback Turing machines for each computable ordinal \(\alpha \). We also describe feedback computable and semi-computable sets using inductive definitions and Gale–Stewart games.
Access this chapter
Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout
Purchases are for personal use only
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
- 1.
See the definition of subcomputation trees below.
References
Ackerman, N.L., Freer, C.E., Lubarsky, R.S.: Feedback computability on cantor space 15(2), 7:1–7:18
Ackerman, N.L., Freer, C.E., Lubarsky, R.S.: Feedback turing computability, and turing computability as feedback. In: 30th Annual ACM/IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, pp. 523–534 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1109/LICS.2015.55
Ackerman, N.L., Freer, C.E., Lubarsky, R.S.: An introduction to feedback turing computability 30(1), 27–6. https://doi.org/10.1093/logcom/exaa002
Aguilera, J.P., Lubarsky, R.S.: Feedback hyperjump 31(1), 20–39.https://doi.org/10.1093/logcom/exaa085
Aguilera, J.P., Soto, M.: Type-2 feedback computability
Bradfield, J.C.: Fixpoints, games and the difference hierarchy 37(1), 1. https://doi.org/10.1051/ita:2003011
Bradfield, J.C.: The modal mu-calculus alternation hierarchy is strict 195(2), 133–15. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0304-3975(97)00217-X
Bradfield, J.C., Duparc, J., Quickert, S.: Fixpoint alternation and the Wadge hierarchy. https://www.julianbradfield.org/Research/fixwadge.pdf
Bradfield, J., Duparc, J., Quickert, S.: Transfinite extension of the Mu-calculus. In: Ong, L. (ed.) CSL 2005. LNCS, vol. 3634, pp. 384–396. Springer, Heidelberg (2005). https://doi.org/10.1007/11538363_27
Kozen, D.: Results on the propositional \(\mu \)-calculus 27(3), 333–3. https://doi.org/10.1016/0304-3975(82)90125-6
Lubarsky, R.S.: ITTMs with feedback. In: Schlinder, R. (ed.) Ways of Proof Theory, pp. 341–354
Lubarsky, R.S.: \(\mu \)-definable sets of integers 58(1), 291–313.https://doi.org/10.2307/2275338
Möllerfeld, M.: Generalized inductive definitions: the \(\mu \)-calculus and \(\varPi \)\(^{1}_2\)-comprehension
Moschovakis, Y.: Descriptive Set Theory, Mathematical Surveys and Monographs, vol. 155. American Mathematical Society. https://doi.org/10.1090/surv/155
Rogers, H.: Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability
Welch, P.: \({\rm G}_{\delta \sigma }\)-games and generalized computation. https://arxiv.org/abs/1509. 09135
Acknowledgments
This study was funded by FWF project TAI-797.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Editor information
Editors and Affiliations
Ethics declarations
Disclosure of Interests
The authors have no competing interests to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.
A Proof of Theorem 2
A Proof of Theorem 2
Let \(A\subseteq \omega \) and \(\alpha <\omega _1^\textrm{ck}\). We show that, if A is \(\varSigma ^\mu _{\alpha }\)-definable, then A is \(\alpha \)-feedback semi-computable.
We begin by defining an evaluation function \(\texttt{eval}\) for \(\varSigma ^\mu _\alpha \)-formulas. We then prove by induction on \(\beta \le \alpha \) that the \(\varSigma ^\mu _\beta \)-definable sets are \(\alpha \)-feedback semi-computable.
For this proof, we work with a fixed set of set variables \(\{X_i\mid i\in \omega \}\). We also assume that the \(\mu \)-formulas are in normal form. We do not consider formulas with free number variables. \(\texttt{eval}\) is defined by recursion on the structure of the \(\varSigma ^\mu _\alpha \)-formulas: we begin at the first order formulas and go up level-by-level.
The function \(\texttt{eval}(\varphi ,s)\) takes as input a formula \(\varphi \), and a sequence s of natural numbers. The sequence s is a sequence of indices of (possibly partial) characteristic function of sets. If \(i< \textrm{length}(s)\) then \(s_i\) denotes the index in the ith position of s. If \(i\ge \textrm{length}(s)\), then \(s_i\) is the index for the characteristic function of the empty set. s will be useful when evaluating the fixed-point operators.
We define \(\texttt{eval}\) for first-order formulas, along with auxiliary functions \(\texttt{exists}\) and \(\texttt{forall}\):
-
\(\texttt{eval}(t=t', s) := \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1, &{} \text {if}\ t = t' \\ 0, &{} \text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \)
-
\(\texttt{eval}(t\in X_i, s) := \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1, &{} \text {if}\ {\langle s_i \rangle }^\alpha (t) = 1 \\ 0, &{} \text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \)
-
\(\texttt{eval}(\lnot \psi , s) := \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1, &{} \text {if}\ \texttt{eval}(\psi ,s) = 0 \\ 0, &{} \text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \)
-
\(\texttt{eval}(\psi \wedge \theta , s) := \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1, &{} \text {if}\ \texttt{eval}(\psi ,s) = \texttt{eval}(\theta ,s) = 1 \\ 0, &{} \text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \)
-
\(\texttt{eval}(\psi \vee \theta , s) := \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1, &{} \text {if}\ \texttt{eval}(\psi ,s) = 1 or \texttt{eval}(\theta ,s) = 1 \\ 0, &{} \text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \)
-
\(\texttt{forall}(\psi (x), s, i) := \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 0, &{} \text {if}\ \texttt{eval}(\psi (i),s) = 0 \\ \texttt{forall}(\psi (x), s, i+1), &{} \text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \)
-
\(\texttt{eval}(\forall x.\psi , s) := \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1, &{} \text {if}\ \texttt{forall}(\psi (x), s, 0)\ \text {diverges} \\ 0, &{} \text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \)
-
\(\texttt{exists}(\psi (x), s, i) := \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1, &{} \text {if}\ \texttt{eval}(\psi (i),s) = 1 \\ \texttt{exists}(\psi (x),s,i+1), &{} \text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \)
-
\(\texttt{eval}(\exists x.\psi , s) := \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1, &{} \text {if }\ \texttt{exists}(\psi (x), s,0)\ \text {converges}\\ 0, &{} \text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \)
On \(\texttt{forall}\) and \(\texttt{exists}\), \(\psi (i)\) is obtained by substituting the indicated number variable x by i.
We similarly define \(\texttt{eval}\) on infinitary formulas using auxiliary functions \(\texttt{conjunction}\) and \(\texttt{disjunction}\):
-
\(\texttt{disjunction}(\bigvee _{i\in \omega }\psi _i, s,i) := \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1, &{} \text {if}\ \texttt{eval}(\psi _i,s) = 1\\ \texttt{disjunction}(\bigvee _{i\in \omega }\psi _i, s,i+1), &{} \text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \)
-
\(\texttt{eval}(\bigvee _{i\in \omega }\psi _i, s) := \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1, &{} \text {if}\ \texttt{disjunction}(\bigvee _{i\in \omega }\psi _i, s,0) \text {converges} \\ 0, &{} \text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \)
-
\(\texttt{conjunction}(\bigwedge _{i\in \omega }\psi _i, s,i) := \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 0, &{} \text {if}\ \texttt{eval}(\psi (i),s) = 0\\ \texttt{conjunction}(\bigwedge _{i\in \omega }, s,i+1), &{} \text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \)
-
\(\texttt{eval}(\bigwedge _{i\in \omega }\psi _i, s) := \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 0, &{} \text {if}\ \texttt{conjunction}(\bigwedge _{i\in \omega }\psi _i, s,0) \text {converges} \\ 1, &{} \text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \)
Remember that as we only allow recursively enumerable conjunctions and disjunctions, we can recover \(\psi _i\) from a code of \(\bigwedge _{i\in \omega }\psi _i\) or \(\bigvee _{i\in \omega }\psi _i\).
We now extend \(\texttt{eval}\) to formulas with fixed-points. Suppose \(t\in \mu xX.\psi \) is a \(\varSigma ^\mu _{\beta +1}\)-formula, define:
Where \(s[X:=\emptyset ]\) is obtained by putting an index for the empty set in the ith position of s, and \(s[X_i:=\mu xX.\psi ]\) is obtained by putting an index for \(\lambda n.\texttt{eval}(n\in \mu x_iX_i.\psi )\) in the ith position of s. If s becomes a longer sequence by this procedure, fill the unused positions of s with indexes for the empty set.
If we have extended \(\texttt{eval}\) to \(\varSigma ^\mu _\beta \)-formulas, extend it to \(\varPi ^\mu _\beta \)-formulas by:
This finishes the definition of \(\texttt{eval}\).
We prove by bounded induction on \(\beta \le \alpha \) that the \(\varSigma ^\mu _\beta \)-definable sets are \(\alpha \)-feedback semi-computable. We slightly strengthen the induction hypothesis to show that, for \(\beta <\alpha \), \(\varPi ^\mu _\beta \)-definable sets are \(\alpha \)-feedback computable.
Rights and permissions
Copyright information
© 2024 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG
About this paper
Cite this paper
Aguilera, J.P., Lubarsky, R.S., Pacheco, L. (2024). Higher-Order Feedback Computation. In: Levy Patey, L., Pimentel, E., Galeotti, L., Manea, F. (eds) Twenty Years of Theoretical and Practical Synergies. CiE 2024. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol 14773. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-64309-5_24
Download citation
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-64309-5_24
Published:
Publisher Name: Springer, Cham
Print ISBN: 978-3-031-64308-8
Online ISBN: 978-3-031-64309-5
eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)