Poetry and (the Philosophy of) Ordinary Language
A special issue of Philosophies (ISSN 2409-9287).
Deadline for manuscript submissions: closed (15 October 2024) | Viewed by 8430
Special Issue Editor
Special Issue Information
Dear Colleagues,
Poetry is a creation of ordinary words put to extraordinary use. How do we understand poetry’s power to defamiliarize ordinary language and render it anew, as well as the world it is entangled with? And does the philosophy of ordinary language (Wittgenstein) or ordinary language philosophy (Austin), in so far as these are different, have anything to contribute to our understanding of this question? [1] Furthermore, could poetry itself be understood as a philosophy of ordinary language; hence, a philosophy of what philosophers call the ordinary lifeworld?
Such questions are motivated by the appearance in recent decades of a series of books that attempt to straddle the two sides of what Plato referred to as “an ancient quarrel between [poetry] and philosophy” [2]. These works are, in order of publication, Stanley Cavell’s In Quest of the Ordinary (1988), Marjorie Perloff’s Wittgenstein’s Ladder: Poetic Language and the Strangeness of the Ordinary (1996), and Toril Moi’s Revolution of the Ordinary: Literary Studies After Wittgenstein, Austin and Cavell (2017). A common feature of all three volumes is an invocation of the thought of Ludwig Wittgenstein—arguably the most influential and, we might say, the most artistic philosopher of the twentieth century [3]—as making available a space referred to as “the ordinary”, in which the question of the relation of poetry and philosophy can be most fruitfully explored. And, we might add, these writers explore the ordinary by way of exploring the significance and conditions of ordinary language.
Of particular interest for this Special Issue of the journal is the following remark by Wittgenstein:
Ich glaube meine Stellung zur Philosophie dadurch zusammengefaßt zu haben, indem ich sagte: Philosophie dürtfe man eigentlich nur dichten. Daraus muß sich, sicht scheint mir, ergeben, wie weit mein Denken der Gegenwart, Zukunft, oder der Vergangeneheit angehört. Denn ich habe mich damit auch als einen bekannt, der micht ganz kann was er zu können wünscht.
[I believe to have summed up my attitude towards philosophy in that I said: one should really only create philosophy poetically. That, it seems to me, should reveal the extent to which my thinking belongs to the present, the future or the past. For with that I have also revealed myself as someone who can't quite do what he would like to be able to do [4].]
The crucial sentence is “Philosophie dürtfe man eigentlich nur dichten.” How should we interpret that in context? Majorie Perloff, a native German speaker, writes the following:
Wittgenstein's proposition, as I have noted elsewhere (Perloff 2004, 53 n. 12) is all but untranslatable, because there is no precise English equivalent of the German verb dichten—a verb that means to create poetry but also, in the wider sense, to produce something fictional, as in Goethe's Dichtung und Wahrheit, where fiction is opposed to truth. My own earlier translation: “Philosophy ought really to be written as a form of poetry” (Perloff 1996, xviii and passim) is not quite accurate, since there is no reference to form of writing here. Peter Winch, whose first edition of CV [Culture and Value] renders Wittgenstein's sentence as ‘Philosophy ought really to be written only as a poetic composition,’ revises it for the 1998 edition to read ‘Really one should write philosophy only as one writes a poem.’ The word “poem” is misleading—Wittgenstein did not, after all, write poems—and perhaps the most accurate translation is David Schalkwyk's: ‘Philosophy should be written only as one would write poetry’ (2004, 56). Or, to be even more colloquial, one can follow David Antin's ‘One should really only do philosophy as poetry’ (1998, 161)” [5].
Even after taking into account this sensitivity to the matter of translation, we are left with the following question: How is philosophy to be written poetically? [6] One suggestion is that philosophy, as Wittgentein practices it, can aspire to a form of poetry—say, in its use of assertoric language for non-assertoric (non-informational, non-factual) purposes. Another intriguing possibility is that poetry can be a form of philosophy—where philosophy is, following Wittgenstein, a non-doctrinal activity of recovering a sense of disorientation in the realm of meaning and meaning making in language. Both poetic philosophy and philosophical poetry will be explored in this Special Issue.
In his interpretation of Wittgenstein, Stanley Cavell elaborates on what Wittgenstein calls “the everyday” or “the ordinary” as ordinary language understood in terms of the everyday criteria we unselfconsciously use to apply concepts to the world in linguistic practice [7]. Wittgenstein distinguishes language that is doing “work”—that is, language that is used within “language-games”—from language that is “on holiday”.[8] But the philosophical attempt to understand the work language does and its conditions faces significant obstacles. He remarks the following:
A main source of our failure to understand is that we do not command a clear view of the use of our words.—Our grammar is lacking in this sort of perspicuity [9].
We are not at all prepared for the task of describing the use of the word e.g., “to think” [10].
Two ideas of ordinary language are present here: (1) That we are unaware of how ordinary language operates—we have no rule book of correct use or catalogue of our criteria for concepts of “objects”. We might add that what native speakers have is more a kind of know-how than a theoretical knowledge of language. (2) Ordinary language is not something stable and fixed but a complex flux of the creative use we make of ordinary words in specific contexts in second-personal space, i.e., the space of person-to-person communication. In language we are all improvising our lives together.
In Wittgenstein’s view, philosophy attempts to explain language from a God’s-eye-view (or, more prosaically, from the armchair) when it should rest content to describe it—where what he means is to describe not idiosyncratic psychological effects of language but its “logic”. What is in question is the informal logic of language which is not a matter of rules or conventions but something whose shifting significances we keep track of in our practices of using it. Poetry’s creations in ordinary words call attention to their imaginative power and to the worldly background against which making meaning in language is possible—the taken-for-granted, the obvious, a sense of the way things normally happen or do not happen. Even if it invokes magic, myth, and fantasy, poetry maintains its grip on reality [11].
In this Special Issue exploring the relationship between poetry and ordinary (hence, extraordinary) language, we have invited philosophers from diverse backgrounds, as well as poets who are also philosophers of poetry. Each approaches the question of the relation of poetry to ordinary language in a unique way. What poetry is and what ordinary language is—as well as what the ordinary world presupposed and pictured in ordinary language is—are all in question in these papers. Since I want to let each contributor speak for themselves, I will only provide the barest sketch of their contribution here.
Justin Clemens gives a close reading of a few lines of John Milton’s Lycidas concerning poetry and the ordinary. Sophie-Grace Chappell writes on the Oedipus complex and the way in which Oedipus is resistant to the extraordinary in Sophocles’s Oedipus Tyrannus. Chappell is also including her new English translation of four of Horace’s Odes, which are an attempt to perform philosophy in poetry. Max Deutscher composes a response to Paul Celan on speeches about poetry. Julian Lamb applies the ordinary language philosopher J. L. Austin’s notion of performative utterance to a passage from Shakespeare’s Romeo & Juliet. David Macarthur discusses poetry as a form of anti-skeptical philosophy, giving a close reading of Czeslaw Milosz’s Realism in which “realism” is understood as an attitude to the ordinary in contrast to, and contesting, “realism” as a metaphysical or epistemological doctrine. Paul Magee’s paper compares innovation in ordinary language with innovation in poetry and poetry criticism. David Musgrave explores the difference between what is said and what is shown in the poetry of W. H. Auden and Kenneth Goldsmith, pursuing the latter’s practice with a “found poem” in a versification of G. E. Moore’s “proof” of an external world in the face of skepticism. And Lucy Van writes about the beginning of a poem in a meditation on quotation and the questions about originality, difference, tradition, context, and improvisation it gives rise to.
Contributors
Justin Clemens is Associate Professor of Philosophy, Univesity of Melbourne.
Sophie Grace Chappell is Professor of Philosophy, Open University.
Max Deutscher is Emeritus Professor of Philosophy, Macquarie University.
Julian Lamb is Senior Lecturer in Liberal Arts, University of Wollongong.
David Macarthur is Professor of Philosophy, University of Sydney.
David Musgrave is Senior Lecturer in Creative Writing, University of Newcastle.
Paul Magee is Professor of Poetry, University of Canberra.
Lucy Van is Research Associate, University of Melbourne.
Notes and References
[1] There are reasons for thinking Wittgenstein’s thought cannot be captured in any school of ideas which is one reason for denying that he is an ordinary language philosopher, of Austin’s ilk. Wittgenstein himself writes, “(The philosopher is not a member of any community of ideas. That is what makes him a philosopher.)” Ludwig Wittgenstein, Zettel, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe. (London: Basil Blackwell, 1967), §455.
[2] Plato, The Republic, in Plato: The Complete Words ed. John M. Cooper. (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1997), Book X, 607b.
[3] Rudolph Carnap writes, “His point of view and his attitude toward people and problems… were much more similar to those of a creative artist than to those of a scientist; one might almost say similar to those of a religious prophet or a seer.” Quoted in Ray Monk, The Duty of Genius. (London: Penguin, 1990), 244.
[4] Ludwig Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, revised ed. (Chicago University of Chicago Press, 1998), 28. I want to thank Carl Godfrey for this translation.
[5] Marjorie Perloff, “Writing Philosophy as Poetry: Literary Form in Wittgenstein,” The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein, ed. Oscari Kuusela and Marie McGinn. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 11. References to papers by Schalkwyks and Antin can be found in Perloff’s article.
[6] Marjorie Perloff writes, “But how the two are related, how philosophy is to be written only as poetry: this remains a puzzle, not just for Wittgenstein's reader, but for the philosopher himself.” Ibid., 2.
[7] Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations 4th ed. Trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, P. Hacker & J. Schulte (Oxford: Blackwell, 2009), §19. Stanley Cavell, The Claim of Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979).
[8] Wittgenstein, Investigations, §132, §7, §38.
[9] Ibid., §122.
[10] Ludwig Wittgenstein, Zettel, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell, 1967, §111.
[11] See Cora Diamond, The Realistic Spirit (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991), 39.
Prof. Dr. David Macarthur
Guest Editor
Manuscript Submission Information
Manuscripts should be submitted online at www.mdpi.com by registering and logging in to this website. Once you are registered, click here to go to the submission form. Manuscripts can be submitted until the deadline. All submissions that pass pre-check are peer-reviewed. Accepted papers will be published continuously in the journal (as soon as accepted) and will be listed together on the special issue website. Research articles, review articles as well as short communications are invited. For planned papers, a title and short abstract (about 100 words) can be sent to the Editorial Office for announcement on this website.
Submitted manuscripts should not have been published previously, nor be under consideration for publication elsewhere (except conference proceedings papers). All manuscripts are thoroughly refereed through a double-blind peer-review process. A guide for authors and other relevant information for submission of manuscripts is available on the Instructions for Authors page. Philosophies is an international peer-reviewed open access semimonthly journal published by MDPI.
Please visit the Instructions for Authors page before submitting a manuscript. The Article Processing Charge (APC) for publication in this open access journal is 1400 CHF (Swiss Francs). Submitted papers should be well formatted and use good English. Authors may use MDPI's English editing service prior to publication or during author revisions.
Keywords
- poetry
- philosophy
- Plato
Benefits of Publishing in a Special Issue
- Ease of navigation: Grouping papers by topic helps scholars navigate broad scope journals more efficiently.
- Greater discoverability: Special Issues support the reach and impact of scientific research. Articles in Special Issues are more discoverable and cited more frequently.
- Expansion of research network: Special Issues facilitate connections among authors, fostering scientific collaborations.
- External promotion: Articles in Special Issues are often promoted through the journal's social media, increasing their visibility.
- e-Book format: Special Issues with more than 10 articles can be published as dedicated e-books, ensuring wide and rapid dissemination.
Further information on MDPI's Special Issue polices can be found here.