[go: up one dir, main page]
More Web Proxy on the site http://driver.im/

Ind-completion

(Redirected from Ind-object)

In mathematics, the ind-completion or ind-construction is the process of freely adding filtered colimits to a given category C. The objects in this ind-completed category, denoted Ind(C), are known as direct systems, they are functors from a small filtered category I to C.

The dual concept is the pro-completion, Pro(C).

Definitions

edit

Filtered categories

edit

Direct systems depend on the notion of filtered categories. For example, the category N, whose objects are natural numbers, and with exactly one morphism from n to m whenever  , is a filtered category.

Direct systems

edit

A direct system or an ind-object in a category C is defined to be a functor

 

from a small filtered category I to C. For example, if I is the category N mentioned above, this datum is equivalent to a sequence

 

of objects in C together with morphisms as displayed.

The ind-completion

edit

Ind-objects in C form a category ind-C.

Two ind-objects

 

and

  determine a functor

Iop x J   Sets,

namely the functor

 

The set of morphisms between F and G in Ind(C) is defined to be the colimit of this functor in the second variable, followed by the limit in the first variable:

 

More colloquially, this means that a morphism consists of a collection of maps   for each i, where   is (depending on i) large enough.

Relation between C and Ind(C)

edit

The final category I = {*} consisting of a single object * and only its identity morphism is an example of a filtered category. In particular, any object X in C gives rise to a functor

 

and therefore to a functor

 

This functor is, as a direct consequence of the definitions, fully faithful. Therefore Ind(C) can be regarded as a larger category than C.

Conversely, there need not in general be a natural functor

 

However, if C possesses all filtered colimits (also known as direct limits), then sending an ind-object   (for some filtered category I) to its colimit

 

does give such a functor, which however is not in general an equivalence. Thus, even if C already has all filtered colimits, Ind(C) is a strictly larger category than C.

Objects in Ind(C) can be thought of as formal direct limits, so that some authors also denote such objects by

 

This notation is due to Pierre Deligne.[1]

Universal property of the ind-completion

edit

The passage from a category C to Ind(C) amounts to freely adding filtered colimits to the category. This is why the construction is also referred to as the ind-completion of C. This is made precise by the following assertion: any functor   taking values in a category D that has all filtered colimits extends to a functor   that is uniquely determined by the requirements that its value on C is the original functor F and such that it preserves all filtered colimits.

Basic properties of ind-categories

edit

Compact objects

edit

Essentially by design of the morphisms in Ind(C), any object X of C is compact when regarded as an object of Ind(C), i.e., the corepresentable functor

 

preserves filtered colimits. This holds true no matter what C or the object X is, in contrast to the fact that X need not be compact in C. Conversely, any compact object in Ind(C) arises as the image of an object in X.

A category C is called compactly generated, if it is equivalent to   for some small category  . The ind-completion of the category FinSet of finite sets is the category of all sets. Similarly, if C is the category of finitely generated groups, ind-C is equivalent to the category of all groups.

Recognizing ind-completions

edit

These identifications rely on the following facts: as was mentioned above, any functor   taking values in a category D that has all filtered colimits, has an extension

 

that preserves filtered colimits. This extension is unique up to equivalence. First, this functor   is essentially surjective if any object in D can be expressed as a filtered colimits of objects of the form   for appropriate objects c in C. Second,   is fully faithful if and only if the original functor F is fully faithful and if F sends arbitrary objects in C to compact objects in D.

Applying these facts to, say, the inclusion functor

 

the equivalence

 

expresses the fact that any set is the filtered colimit of finite sets (for example, any set is the union of its finite subsets, which is a filtered system) and moreover, that any finite set is compact when regarded as an object of Set.

The pro-completion

edit

Like other categorical notions and constructions, the ind-completion admits a dual known as the pro-completion: the category Pro(C) is defined in terms of ind-object as

 

(The definition of pro-C is due to Grothendieck (1960).[2])

Therefore, the objects of Pro(C) are inverse systems or pro-objects in C. By definition, these are direct system in the opposite category   or, equivalently, functors

 

from a small cofiltered category I.

Examples of pro-categories

edit

While Pro(C) exists for any category C, several special cases are noteworthy because of connections to other mathematical notions.

The appearance of topological notions in these pro-categories can be traced to the equivalence, which is itself a special case of Stone duality,

 

which sends a finite set to the power set (regarded as a finite Boolean algebra). The duality between pro- and ind-objects and known description of ind-completions also give rise to descriptions of certain opposite categories. For example, such considerations can be used to show that the opposite category of the category of vector spaces (over a fixed field) is equivalent to the category of linearly compact vector spaces and continuous linear maps between them.[4]

Applications

edit

Pro-completions are less prominent than ind-completions, but applications include shape theory. Pro-objects also arise via their connection to pro-representable functors, for example in Grothendieck's Galois theory, and also in Schlessinger's criterion in deformation theory.

edit

Tate objects are a mixture of ind- and pro-objects.

Infinity-categorical variants

edit

The ind-completion (and, dually, the pro-completion) has been extended to ∞-categories by Lurie (2009).

See also

edit

Notes

edit
  1. ^ Illusie, Luc, From Pierre Deligne’s secret garden: looking back at some of his letters, Japanese Journal of Mathematics, vol. 10, pp. 237–248 (2015)
  2. ^ C.E. Aull; R. Lowen (31 December 2001). Handbook of the History of General Topology. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 1147. ISBN 978-0-7923-6970-7.
  3. ^ Johnstone (1982, §VI.2)
  4. ^ Bergman & Hausknecht (1996, Prop. 24.8)

References

edit