1. Introduction
Quantum mechanics works perfectly and is reliable in an appropriate regime. Nevertheless, it leaves us with cognitive discomfort, as a theory that pretends to be fundamental should describe whole physical reality, including the classical objective properties of the systems that are inter-subjectively verifiable by independent observers. The problem is that quantum formalism does not offer a simple footbridge from the quantum world to our actual world. This issue involves many aspects; it has a long history and huge literature [
1]. In particular, it involves a highly non-trivial question: Is it possible to circumvent the fundamental restrictions (no-broadcasting [
2,
3]) on the processing of quantum information to explain the emergence of the objective nature of information redundancy in the actual world?
Thanks to Zurek’s quantum Darwinism concept [
4], there are strong reasons to believe that the decoherence theory pioneered by Zeh [
5] and developed by Zurek [
6,
7] and others [
8,
9] based on the system–environment (or, in the Bohr’s spirit: system–context [
10]) paradigm offers the most promising approach to the emergence of classicality from the quantum world.
Quantum Darwinism (QD) considers a decohering environment
E as a “witness” that monitors and can reveal the information about a system
. The environment consists of multiple independent N fragments, and objectivity emerges when interacting with the system led to redundant information proliferation about system
measured by quantum mutual information
between the system and an accessible fragment of the environment,
, where
is the mutual information between the system and part of the environment and
is the von Neumann entropy (see [
11] and the references therein). The term “objectivity” means that the state of the system satisfies the following:
Definition 1. A system state is objective when many independent observers can determine the state of S independently, without perturbing it, and arrive at the same result [12,13,14]. The different theoretical and experimental implementations of QD have been considered and discussed based on the information-theoretic condition:
In many cases, the above relation is sufficient to identify correctly emergent objective properties in a quantum system in contact with an environment. Interestingly, sometimes the nature of the quantum-classical interplay may be richer. In particular, examples have been found in which QD can falsely announce objectivity, and it has been indicated that QD can be inconsistent with the emergence of objectivity when the condition (
1) is used [
14,
15,
16].
In connection with the QD, a problem arises:
To identify quantum primitive information broadcasting state responsible for the emergence of the perceived objectivity. This issue was raised in [
14], where it was proven that Bohr’s non-disturbance measurement, full decoherence and “strong independence” lead to the paradigmatic spectrum broadcast structure (SBS) responsible for objectivity, which can be written in the following form:
where
is the accessible environment,
,
,
are the subenvironments. The conditional states
can be used to perfectly distinguish index
i, where
is some diagonal basis of the
and
its spectrum.
The basis
has a special role in the above picture. It represents the objective information about the quantum system. The above form (
2) is agnostic about the physical mechanism leading to it. Hence, we shall call the basis
a
generalised pointer basis (or, alternatively an
indicator basis). In the case of quantum Darwinism, when determined by the interaction Hamiltonian, this basis becomes exactly the pointer basis. However, there may be other physical processes that lead to the above (
2) structure. This is directly related to the main point of the present paper: any pointer basis is the generalized pointer basis but
not vice versa.
The above SBS state clearly shows the meaning of the terms “objective”/inter-subjective used in Definition 1. This reveals the contextual nature of objectivity, which emerges as a property of a system dependent on the combined properties of the system and the environment. These states have a discord of zero; hence, only the “classic” spectrum of the system is broadcast to the environment, and therefore independent observers do not have access to quantum information.
It has been proven that SBS is a stronger condition than the QD, i.e., SBS implies QD [
14]. The objective states with spectrum broadcast structure can be used as ideal “frames of reference” to which any real states can be compared. The SBS was identified in the many models of open quantum systems (see [
17] and the references therein), and its simulations on a quantum computer were demonstrated [
18]. It was also shown that the objectivity is subjective across quantum reference frames [
19], including its dynamical aspects [
20].
It was mentioned in [
14] that the SBS-like states may open a “classical window” for life processes within the quantum world. Interestingly, the process of objectivization of information over time was analysed using quantum state discrimination and potential applications for the theory of evolution of senses were suggested [
12]. Remarkably, in nature, there are thermal states the properties of which, seem to contradict objectivity suggesting that thermality and objectivity are mutually exclusive. Recently Le et al. [
21] examined the overlap between thermal and objective states and showed that there are certain regimes in which exist states that are approximately thermal and objective.
As mentioned above, the SBS implies quantum Darwinism condition (
1); however, the opposite implication does not hold. The discrepancy between the QD and SBS led to the discovery of a stronger version of quantum Darwinism (SQD) [
22], where (
1) is replaced by a stronger condition: A system state is objective if the following conditions hold simultaneously:
where
is the Holevo information in the pointer basis
,
is the accessible information and
is the conditional multipartite mutual information. It has been shown that SQD is equivalent to bipartite SBS, and it is sufficient and necessary for objectivity [
22,
23,
24]. Thus, SBS and SQD are two extensions of the standard QD based on the quantum state structure and information, respectively [
25].
However, in the limit of a large environment the standard QD works very well. In [
11], the authors investigated a model based on imperfect C-NOT gates and showed that relevant quantities for QD exhibited similar dependence on the size
of a fragment of environment
, including scaling independent from the quality of the imperfect C-NOT gates and the size of the fragment of environment
.
2. Aspects of Emergence of Objective Information on Quantum Ground
The fundamental elements of Zurek’s quantum Darwinism discovery were (1) The methodological identification that classical correlations between the system and environment and redundant character of the information about the system in the environment are a constitutive feature of objectivity. (2) Proof that this objective information is very special, unambiguously determined by a system–environment interaction. More precisely, the interaction chooses a basis, called the pointer basis, and this is the information concerning the question “In which state of the pointer basis is the system in?” that is replicated by interaction in the environment in a stable way. Quite remarkably, the latter feature is responsible for the strong cognitive power of the whole process.
This is the case for the following three reasons. First, the information-theoretic correlations between the system and parts of the environment have a classical, well-understood character. Second, a subject observing a part of the environment not only knows that the system is in some particular state but also knows exactly what the system state is, since the latter belongs to a special basis—the pointer basis. Third, by a repetition of an experiment of placing the system in the same state many times into the environment and observing some part of the latter, the subject is also able to learn (via a collection of the experiment statistics) about some parameters of the initial state of the system.
These correspond to the diagonal of the state written in the pointer basis. The parameters are revealed in this process. In this sense, we may understand the quantum Darwinism process as a process of objectivization that discloses the parameters of the system state.
In the present paper, we inquire as to whether and when the dynamical emergence of objectivity is possible in a more relaxed sense—namely, when one retains only the element (1) of Zurek’s program. More precisely, we only demand that the information about the system being in one of the elements of some basis is classically present in the environment—there are only classical correlations between system and environment. However neither the basis needs to be directly related to the system–environment interaction nor do the corresponding statistics need to directly correspond to some particular parameters of the initial state of the system. In this sense, the basis has only the character of the generalized pointer basis (see discussion below (
2)).
Below, we show that this kind of objectivization can emerge in low-dimensional qubit systems. For this purpose, we examine the non-perfect propagation of information from system to the noisy environment with self-evolution and analyse interrelations between the degree of objectivization and environment parameters. We consider two different environments, the first composed of one observed and one unobserved qubit and the second one where there are seven observed qubits and one unobserved.
In particular, we consider an analytical model of three interacting qubits and derive its objectivity parameters. Then, we show that, if the imperfection of the C-NOT gate is known, the emergence of the objectivity albeit with respect to a different basis than the one associated with the gate itself—can be triggered by carefully chosen environment self-dynamics. For a seven-qubit environment, numerical calculations show that dynamics of the environment may help the emergence of relaxed objectivity to happen.
3. Analytical Model for Three Interacting Qubits
Let us now investigate a model of three interacting qubits, where we consider one of them as the observed system, and the remaining two constitute the observing environment . In the following, we will derive a closed analytical formula for the objectivity parameters, viz. decoherence and orthogonalization, in a scenario where the information is widespread using imperfect C-NOT gate (C-INOT gate), and where the time evolution includes self-evolution of each of the qubits and their inter-environmental interaction.
3.1. Derivation of Objectivity Parameters
We model the C-INOT gates [
11] defined by the formula:
where
is the imperfection parameter. For
, the gate reproduces the perfect C-NOT gate. It does not allow to model the two qubit identity unitary. In this work, we have chosen the Kronecker product convention where the primal structure of the matrix representation is determined by the first space involved in the product.
There is an infinite number of Hamiltonians that can realise the gate (
4) after some fixed time of interaction. Here, we choose the following Hamiltonian:
One may check that
for
. We denote by
,
, the Hamiltonians of C-INOT acting on the first and second qubits of the environment, respectively, conditioned by the system bit.
We assume that the total Hamiltonian is given by:
where
with
denoting identity on a single qubit space. Here,
is the self-evolution Hamiltonian of the central system;
is the self-evolution of the environmental qubits that can be, e.g., caused by an external magnetic field;
contains inter-qubit interactions, between each pair of the qubits plus the joint interaction between all three qubits via
and
coupling, respectively.
are the interaction strength parameters.
Whereas (
7b) easily generalizes for cases with more qubits in the environment, (
7c) is specific for the two-qubit case. Further in this paper, we consider other inter-environmental interactions with larger environments.
One can rewrite
with
being the 3-qubit identity operator, and
M a block-diagonal matrix, giving
also of block-diagonal form, with blocks denoted by
and
. The explicit form of those matrices is given in
Appendix A.
We assume that the initial system–environment state
is given by:
where
are the environment qubit states,
.
We note that, for
the state
is the termal state of the environment and
, or
, where
is the inverse temperature. This holds because of the form of
, i.e. the state
is the ground state of the Hamiltonian. After the time evolution, given by
, the joint state of the system and two qubit environment
in the computational basis of the observed system is
where each element of the 2 × 2 matrix is a block 4 × 4 matrix and
and
,
k = 0, 1. After tracing out the second environmental qubit, we find, again, in the computational basis, the following two qubit joint state of the system and observing qubit:
where
is the second qubit partial trace operation. Hence, we obtain the collective decoherence factor in the form
This equation is the value of the trace norm of a 2 × 2 upper off-diagonal block of the 4 × 4 matrix (
11). The trace norm is defined as
.
The probabilities and of the system being in a state 0 or 1 of the computational basis are given by and are revealed to be constant in time. Conditioning upon the system state in the computational basis and tracing out the second environmental qubit, we find that the conditional states of the remaining (observing) qubit, denoted and , where is a single qubit. Those states are obtained by a projection of the joint state of the system and part of the environment on one of the possible states of the system in the computational basis. If there is no coherence between different states of the system, then the off-diagonal elements should vanish, as is explicitly stated in the definition of SBSs.
The (generalized) fidelity [
26] (also called the Bhattacharyya coefficient), used as a measure of state overlap [
12] for two matrices
and
is defined as
The larger the value of the fidelity, the poorer the orthogonalization of the relevant observable. We provide explicit formulae for (
12) and (
13) in
Appendix B.
The upper bound to the distance to the Spectrum Broadcast Structure [
12,
14] is
which is true for some state
having the SBS form (
2). The bound (
14) can be applied to any state, not only qubit-qubit states. In
Appendix C, we discuss the distance of the evolved state to the thermal state.
3.2. Generalised Pointer Basis Optimal for SBS
Since the constituent Hamiltonians in (
7) do not commute with the C-INOT gate Hamiltonians, one cannot follow the paradigm of [
6] and determine the generalized pointer basis from the interaction Hamiltonian only. In other words, this is the case when the generalized pointer basis (which may also be called the indicator basis) is a different object from the pointer basis known from quantum Darwinism.
Above in (
11), we wrote the evolved state in the computational basis, and the calculations of (
A12) and (
A16) refer to this basis. On the other hand, one may ask the question, whether there exists some other basis of the observed system that manifests structure closer to SBS.
For the two environmental qubit cases with one of them being traced out, we shall look for the optimal SBS state—namely, the one that is the closest to the actual system–environment state represented in the computational basis
(see (
11)). To this aim, we minimize the distance of the latter to the SBS states, which, by definition, have the form:
Note that this form easily generalizes for environments of higher dimension with
and
replaced with orthogonal
and
:
In the two-qubit case, minimisation of the corresponding distance
over all probability
, and state vectors
, and
defining (
15) gives the optimal SBS state:
The basis
for which the minimum of (
17) is attained should be considered as a candidate for the generalised pointer (equiv. indicator) basis for the case when the total Hamiltonian (
6) does not commute with the interaction Hamiltonians (
5).
To be more specific, for
and
being qubits, as in (
15), we use the standard Bloch parametrization
with
,
, and similarly for
. Further, without loss of generality, we assume
. This last assumption assures continuity of the parameters obtained in the optimization, as without it the optimization has two possible equivalent solutions,
viz. the one from (
15) and the second one with
replaced with
and states replaced with their orthogonal complements.
In the actual numerical calculations, we used unconstrained gradient search with a continuous map
for the
parameter, and postprocessing of the resulting optimal values
to obtain angles within the proper Bloch parameter range yielding the same qubit states. We illustrate the optimization of the SBS basis in
Figure 1.
3.3. Marginal Cases
Another interesting marginal case is for maximally mixed environment, i.e., for
. Then,
and
, again leading to
. This is in agreement with [
27], as this case refers to maximal entropy of the environment, and thus its capacity is 0.
For fixed
and
, we see from (
A16) that the orthogonalization factor is a function of
. Thus, by changing the difference
, we can adjust the total Hamiltonian so that the orthogonalization reaches its maximum. Thus, knowing the imperfections of the interaction
, mixedness
p environment, and the internal interaction
, we can, e.g., manipulate the magnetic field
acting on the environment, to improve the quality of the measurement. We illustrate this adjustment in the following section.
4. Central Interaction: Optimization of Spectrum Broadcast Structure for 2 Environmental Qubits
We now consider the case when , and , i.e., with imperfect central interaction and self-evolution of environmental qubits with initial mixedness parameter p after time , viz. at the time after which the central interaction has fully occurred.
We first note that, in the former
Section 3, we considered the Spectrum Broadcast Structure obtained in the pointer basis [
6], which was, in that case, equal to the computational basis of the observed system. Yet, it is possible to calculate the SBS distance for a different basis,
viz. for the optimal basis, as introduced in
Section 3.2.
We used the gradient method [
28] to find the basis that minimizes the SBS distance. We note that the considered setup with only two qubits is very far from the one involving the macroscopic environment, and thus the objectivity present in this model can be only temporary since a single qubit is not able to induce full decoherence that is stable in time or orthogonalization of observables.
Yet, we are interested in the classical properties of the evolved system at a particular time moment, namely, the time that we denote as , the time at which the measurement is supposed to occur. Still, this scenario illustrates the mechanism, and we leave the actual scaling of the discussed non-monotonic phenomena for further research.
We performed the calculation of the SBS distance (
17) for the case with
as a function of self-evolution of the environment parameter
and environmental mixedness, or
noise, parameter
p for various C-INOT imperfection parameter
. The results are shown in
Figure 2. For better readability we show their marginal values for
in
Figure 3a, and for
in
Figure 3b.
We observe that, for , there exist values of that allow improving the SBS structure of the evolved state; thus, the self-evolution can to some extent counter-act the interaction gate imperfections.
For the perfect C-NOT depicted in
Figure 2a, we observe that, for small
p, the self-evolution has a destructive influence on the SBS formation. On the other hand, for large values of
p, adding some self-evolution may improve the SBS structure. This reveals that, for
p close to
, the Hadamard basis is the actual optimal basis for SBS formation. For
, we observe a surprising phenomenon—that increasing the environmental mixedness may also improve the SBS formation.
A similar situation of non-monotonicity in both
and
p can be clearly noticed in
Figure 2b,c refering to imperfect C-NOT with
and
, respectively. For small
with increasing environmental mixedness, the optimal SBS basis approaches the actual computational basis.
For large imperfections of C-NOT, with
,
Figure 2d, we see that the SBS is being destroyed by noise in a monotonic way, but non-monotonicity in
shows that the state is closest to SBS for
.
To better illustrate the non-monotonic phenomena, we depicted the marginal cases in
Figure 3a, where we show the SBS distance depending on
, and in
Figure 3b, where the dependence on
p is plotted.
For the sake of completeness, let us consider another form of the interaction between the two environmental qubits—that is, the neighbour–neighbour interaction
. We plot this dependence in
Figure 4. The same non-monotonic pattern can be seen as in
Figure 2.
Importance of the Basis Choice
In the present section, we illustrate the emergence of different indicator bases than the pointer basis in another way, rougher than the one performed in
Section 3.2. Rather than performing full optimization, we perform a partial one, fixing the first one of the two anticipated bases (standard or Hadamard) and analysing a specific parameter that will tell us which of the bases is closer to the optimum.
To be more specific, in the optimization of the quantity (
17), we allowed for
any SBS basis
of the observed system in the calculation of the minimal distance of
from the SBS set.
Now, let us assume that the basis
is fixed, and the optimization is performed only over pure qubits
and
. To this end, let us define the following subset of SBS states:
We define the distance
of the state
from the set
:
Now, we illustrate the difference between choices of different bases by comparing SBS distance if the basis of the SBS state is fixed to be either in the computational or in the Hadamard basis in (
15). To this end, in
Figure 5, we plot the difference between the minimized SBS-distance in the latter basis subtracted the minimized SBS distance in the former basis,
viz.It can be easily seen that, even if we are not considering the optimal basis from (
18) but restrict to the two simplest choices, the computational and Hadamard, the formation of the SBS structure favours either the former or the latter basis depending on the evolution and environment parameters, even though the pointer basis in quantum Darwinism sense does not change. One must remember that this is a very rough picture if compared to that of
Section 3.2. However, it shows that some tendencies concerning the information about the system encoded in the environment may still be identified despite the use of less computational effort.
5. Central Interaction: Optimization of Spectrum Broadcast Structure for 8 Environmental Qubits
Next, we considered a case with a larger number
of environmental qubits. In this case, we consider the broadcast Hamiltonian to be a sum
where
is defined by (
5) with transformation over
i-th environmental qubit controlled by the central system. We consider only the self-evolution of separate environmental qubits, and thus this is a direct generalization of the three-qubits case with
and arbitrary
. The self-evolution Hamiltonian is (in analogy to the 3-qubit case from
Section 3.1):
where
acts on
i-th environmental qubit.
We performed numerical calculations for an 8-qubit environment. We assumed that 7 of these qubits constitute the observer, with the last qubit being trace-out. In all cases in this section, we considered the optimal SBS basis.
The optimization of (
17) for environments of dimension larger is much more difficult; thus, we were not able to find the state (
16) exactly. Instead, we calculated the upper bound of [
12], cf. (
14) to check if the non-monotonic phenomena that we observed for two qubits can be expected to occur also in this case. The results of the numerical optimization are shown in
Figure 6. The calculated upper bounds suggest that there exists some regime of gate imperfection
, where both self-evolution and noise of the environment can improve the SBS structure as in the case of a two-qubit environment (see
Section 3 and
Section 4).
We stress that the quantity (
14) of [
12] is only an upper bound, even though it can be applied to a state, and is easily computable. The calculation of (
14) is purely algebraic and does not require any optimization procedure. On the other hand, since it provides only an upper bound, the exact results may diverge from those obtained with the bound, yet the similarity of behaviour of the plots obtained with the bound (see
Figure 6) is similar to those derived using optimization of an exact formula (see
Figure 2). This shows that the upper bound is able to properly grasp the non-monotonic tendencies occurring in both scenarios.
For perfect C-NOT, see Equation (
4), with
, for majority values of
the SBS distance is gradually growing with increasing
p, approaching value close to 1 for the maximal mixedness
. For
the SBS distance is also increasing for
. Yet, for large values of
and
p, a slightly non-monotonic behaviour is seen in
p.
For
, a clear improvement in SBS formation with increasing
p can be seen in
Figure 6b, where the optimal value of
is increasing with
p. For
, it can be observed that the SBS is best formed for
, which is also a surprising effect, confirming the previous observation that, with self-evolution of environment, it is possible that more noised (mixed) initial environment is more suitable for SBS formation that the pure environment. Even stronger effect is visible in
Figure 6c. Still, it should be noted that, in those cases the SBS distance upper-bound is very large, close to 1, or even higher, and thus its behaviour may serve only as a preliminary suggestion regarding the behaviour of the actual distance to SBS of the formed states, and as such, should be followed by tight analytical approximations in the future.
In the case of large imperfections of C-INOT,
viz. , see
Figure 6d, a clear effect of improvement in SBS formation for increasing self-evolution of environment parameter
occurs, which is especially strong for small
.
6. Non-Central Interaction for Eight Qubits
Now, let us consider the case with interaction between environmental qubits of the following neighbour–neighbour form:
where
is the number of qubits in the environment, and
acts on
i-th qubit of the environment. We calculated the upper bound [
12] for the case with
and eight qubits as a function of the imperfection of C-INOT parameter
and environmental noise
p. The results are show in
Figure 7. A strong non-monotonicity in
can be observed for low values of
p, e.g., in the case of
, where taking
can repair the effect of C-INOT imperfection.
The analogous situation takes place for fixed where the bound is decreasing with increasing initial noise for the region of 0.1. One should remember, however, that, in this case, the numerical values of the bound are high, and the search for possible non-monotonous behaviour of the exact distance as a function of p should be continued.
7. Conclusions and Discussion
We examined the aspects of the emergence of objective information in the dynamic physical scenario in low-dimensional qubit systems. More precisely, we considered the non-perfect propagation of information from the system to the noisy environment with self-evolution, where the imperfect C-NOT gate [
11] is accompanied by the presence of the self-dynamics of the environment, which—in general—may be in an initially mixed (thermal) state. We considered two different environments, the first composed of one observed and one unobserved qubit and the second one where there are seven observed qubits and one unobserved. In particular, we examined an analytical model of three interacting qubits, and we derived the objectivity parameters.
We considered examples with the system in the Hadamard state and showed that, if the imperfection of the C-NOT gate is known, the emergence of the objectivity—albeit with respect to a different basis than the one associated with the gate itself—can be enhanced by a carefully chosen environment self-dynamics, which may be interpreted only as an external magnetic field. The numerical optimization shows that the quality of the spectrum broadcast structure formed during the interaction may be non-monotonic both in the speed of self-dynamics of the environment as well as its mixedness. We interpret this phenomenon as the emergence of a new type of objectivity, which may be called a relaxed objectivization, since the statistics do not disclose any parameters of the initial state of the system but present to the observer some new ones, generated during the complex dynamical process.
We also discussed the case of eight qubits of environment and numerical calculations supporting the general conjecture, where the dynamics of the environment may help the emergence of objectivity to occur. This suggests that, even if the imperfectness of the C-NOT is large enough to destroy objectivity in the standard scenario [
11], one may observe its “comeback” as a kind of phase transition due to the carefully tuned self-dynamics of the environment.
We believe that the above concept of the relaxed objectivization is interesting in itself because it concerns the general question of whether the system is in fully classical relation with the environment in the philosophical, purely existential sense—namely, that one is allowed to make a sensible claim that some of its property exists. In this sense, the present approach brings out the ontological aspect of emergent objectivity in a quantum world.
The possible cognitive and practical consequences lead two directions. First, if we are in the engineering paradigm, we know that objectivity (technically represented here by the SBS structure) makes the system–environment composition useless for coherent quantum information processing. This may be important in experiments monitoring a general interaction of a given system with a mesoscopic environment, including quantum memory and other coherent effects. In such cases, one should know methods to keep its state far from such an objective form.
The present analysis suggests that it can be done in a simple way—namely, by tuning an external magnetic field. Second, the present analysis may inspire several open questions concerning the possibility of the emergence of objectivity close to the original quantum Darwinism paradigm, yet more relaxed in certain physical scenarios [
29].
For instance, we considered only the situation when the information was objectively “mirrored” in one environment (cf. [
21]). Is it possible to observe the present, relaxed objectivity effect stable in time for a large number of environments as in the case of quantum Darwinism objectivity? If so, is it possible to find situations when, despite the “unfriendly circumstances”—environment dynamics, noise and deviation from the C-NOT gate interaction—the information about some parameters of the initial state of the system can still be easily retrieved from the environment?
Another question would be, whether and when the present objectivised basis can be exploited to read out some well-defined parameters of the whole dynamics. The original pointer basis was defined by a local element, i.e., a system–environment interaction Hamiltonian. Concerning our case: does one need to know all the global dynamics, or are there cases when knowledge of some parameters of the global dynamics (and, perhaps, its particular symmetries) is sufficient to determine our analogue of the pointer basis?
For more than two environments, the SBS structure is stronger than Strong Quantum Darwinism [
22]. However, the concept of generalized pointer basis in those dynamical scenarios where interaction Hamiltonian alone does not determine objectivity may be, in full analogy, defined for Strong Quantum Darwinism, since the latter is also agnostic to the physical mechanism leading to it. The corresponding system environment state satisfying SQD is of a quite general form
but with a special property.
There must exist some isometries that act
locally on the parts of environments
and transform the state
into another state
in such a way that, after tracing out the
parts of the environment, one finds the SBS state defined in (
2) (the domains of the isometries also involve those degrees of freedom that carry possible correlations between different parts of environments but are irrelevant for objectivity). If there are interactions between different parts of the environment, it is likely that objectivity will be encoded in the above general SQD form due to correlations produced by the interactions.
Searching for a generalized pointer basis in a dynamical system may be even more demanding, especially if the environment corresponds already to so-called macrofractions (see [
14]). In those cases, most likely new analytical methods will be needed due to the complexity and numerical intractability of the problem.
Finally, the observed non-monotonicity of objectivity under the parameters of the two potentially “unfriendly” elements of the scenario—the speed of the environment dynamics and mixedness of its states seems counterintuitive. We believe that this requires further investigation in more complex models—both from the SBS as well as SQD perspective—and may lead to some applications that are difficult to identify at this present, early stage of analysis.